Abstract
Parsimony considerations are ubiquitous in the literature concerning the nature of mental states. Other things being equal, physicalist views are preferred over dualist accounts on the grounds of the fact that they do not posit new fundamental properties in addition to the physical ones. This paper calls into question the widespread assumption that parsimony can provide reasons for believing that physicalism is a better candidate than dualism for solving the mind–body problem. After presenting the theoretical core of physicalism and dualism, I make explicit the meta-metaphysical assumptions the physicalist relies on when leveraging parsimony to support her view. In particular, the physicalist takes for granted that parsimony has an epistemic value in metaphysics. This point, however, is rather controversial. I argue that the most promising way to account for the epistemic value of parsimony is to ground it in the epistemic value of modesty, a higher-level theoretical virtue that has to do with the epistemic risk of a theory. Unfortunately for the physicalist, the modesty rationale does not ultimately favour physicalism over dualism.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
I follow Elpidorou (2018) in taking the “nothing over and above” claim to be sufficiently general to capture a number of physicalist positions. Note that I will always refer to physicalism about the nature of mental states. Broader formulations according to which everything is physical lay outside the scope of this paper.
See Ney (2008a) for a critical review of the definitions that have been provided in the literature, and Witmer (2018) for a recent proposal. For simplicity’s sake, unless explicitly stated otherwise, I will take ‘physical’ to be interchangeable with ‘material’. In particular, I will include states of the nervous system—plus the relevant environmental features—in the category of physical states.
See Chalmers (1996, 2010). Note that this view is not incompatible with substance dualism, although Chalmers tends to be cautious when it comes to introducing non-physical particulars as bearers of mental properties. I will not consider such a possibility, and I will take the sui generis mental properties the dualist posits to be instantiated by the same kind of particulars instantiating physical properties.
To be clear, the explanatory argument provides reasons for believing that physicalism is more likely to be true than dualism, without saying anything conclusive. Abduction is by definition a non-demonstrative kind of inference, and in the application to theory choice it can at best provide a justification for preferring one of the given options. Interestingly, nothing prevents us from thinking that both physicalism and dualism are false, that we have simply failed to conceive better options—this is the problem of the unconceived alternatives, formulated in detail by Stanford (2006). In other words, physicalism could turn out to be nothing but the best false theory we have available.
Addressing the issue would require a long detour, but it is noteworthy that parsimony also seems to play a role in the causal argument for physicalism (see Papineau, 2002). In particular, the rejection of systematic overdetermination in cases of mental causation can be regarded as motivated, at least partially, by parsimony considerations concerning the number of individually sufficient causes.
See also Hill (1991), although he is more cautious in making explicit that the strength of such considerations depends on our “aesthetic intuitions” about parsimony.
A clarification has to be made. As widely acknowledged, Melnyk argues that the physicalist cannot assign a high probability to her own view. On the contrary, he argues that current physicalism is likely to be false. This is due to the fact that he opts for the currentist horn of Hempel’s dilemma (see Ney, 2008a). When it comes to providing reasons in favour of physicalism, however, the physicalist à la Melnyk can consistently argue that physicalism, despite being probably false, is still more likely to be true than dualism.
I interpret the notion of question begging as relativized, in the sense that an argument always begs the question against a particular audience (Beebee, 2001).
See Dummett’s (1978) distinction between suasive and explanatory argument.
It is worth mentioning that physicalism is usually understood as a contingent necessitation thesis. It might have been false at the actual world w, but since it is true at w then mental properties are necessitated by physical properties in all possible worlds. As Francescotti (2014, p. 251) clearly states, “while physical facts actually do necessitate mental facts, this need not have been the case”.
Admittedly, this claim is problematic when it comes to grounding. As a matter of fact, some have argued that grounding does not entail necessitation (Leuenberger 2014; Skiles 2015). However, the received view about grounding—provided that there is such a thing—is that grounding carries necessity (Audi 2012; Dasgupta 2014; Rosen 2010; Trogdon 2013).
Since I am focusing on physicalism about the mind, I am narrowing it down to mental states. However, analogous considerations should hold for other domains as well. For example, the physicalist should arguably deny that non-physical fundamental properties are needed to account for chemical and biological phenomena. I cannot afford to go into greater detail, but an interesting question is whether the negative commitment of the physicalist could take the form of a long, potentially open-ended, conjunction of negative claims; on this point, see Wilson (2006).
Note that I take strong emergentists about mental properties to be committed to (Dii); see Chalmers (2006).
Sober (2015) provides a valuable overview of the debate on simplicity principles.
I am admittedly oversimplifying. On the one hand, rigorously speaking, there is little point in arguing that a given theory is simple unless we are implicitly suggesting that it is simpler than other theories. There is no threshold value for calculating simplicity. Simplicity considerations apply on a comparative basis, when two or more theories are contrasted. On the other hand, defining a metric for measuring theories’ simplicity is far from being an easy task; see Scorzato (2013).
Interestingly, Schaffer (2015) argues in favour of a restricted version of Occam’s razor, according to which fundamental entities should not be multiplied without necessity.
Suppose T1 and T2 are equally successful in accounting for the available evidence and allow for the same predictions. Assume that T1 is simpler than T2. In that case, according to van Fraassen, we are justified in preferring T1 in our explanatory practices and when attempting at making predictions, but we have no reason for thinking that T1 is more likely to be true than T2.
I largely follow Schindler (2018) in discussing them.
See Baker (2016), considering the widely discussed case of Einstein’s Special Relativity.
Interestingly, this point is discussed by Sober (2015, pp. 253–260). However, he is skeptical about the dualist’s actual commitment to a model that makes the same prediction as the physicalist’s one.
See Sober (1990), arguing that the rationality of parsimony reduces to ___domain-specific considerations.
Interestingly, an analogous point can be found in the final remarks of Russell (1918/1956).
One may argue that there is a sense in which T1 is not more modest than T2. As a matter of fact, we could fail to discern an intrinsic complexity of the world, and our conviction to be able to explain the relevant phenomena by positing fewer entities (laws, relations, etc.) could be associated with a form of epistemic hybris. In general, I am sympathetic towards this perspective. However, there seems to be no way to determine how complex the investigated phenomena are. Taking for granted that they are intrinsically complex is as immodest as assuming that they are intrinsically simple. Given our ignorance, postulating the existence of fewer entities seems to expose less to error.
See Brenner (2017), arguing that there are no reasons to think that scientific theories cannot be committed to negative existential claims such as those Kriegel has in mind.
Note that, in many cases, it is difficult to assess theories’ overall modesty. Since theories are complex objects, it is perfectly conceivable that, given two theories T1 and T2, T1 is more modest than T2 concerning the postulation of entities but less modest with respect to, say, the causal relations it assumes. At a closer look, however, this should come as no surprise. Simplicity, as we have seen, has at least three different dimensions—qualitative and quantitative parsimony, and elegance. This “makes it impossible to compare theories without first specifying the form of interest” (Schindler, 2018, p. 15; see also McAllister, 1997). I hold that the same applies to modesty considerations, but I agree with Schindler that this does not make such theoretical virtues arbitrary or useless in theory choice.
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.
I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising them.
References
Audi, P. (2012). Grounding: Toward a theory of the in-virtue-of relation. Journal of Philosophy, 109(12), 685–711. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20121091232
Baker, A. (2003). Quantitative parsimony and explanatory power. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54(2), 245–259. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9261-9
Baker, A. (2016). Simplicity. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/simplicity/>.
Barnes, E. C. (2000). Ockham’s razor and the anti-superfluity principle. Erkenntnis, 53(3), 353–374. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1026464713182
Bates, J. (2009). A defence of the explanatory argument for physicalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(235), 315–324. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2008.593.x
Beebee, H. (2001). Transfer of warrant, begging the question, and semantic externalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 51(204), 356–374. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.00234
Bennett, K. (2017). Making things up. OUP.
Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. The Philosophical Review, 108(1), 1–46. https://doi.org/10.2307/2998259
Bottani, A., & Paternoster, A. (2019). Leibniz’s principle and psycho-neural identity. In R. Davies (Ed.), Natural and artifactual objects in contemporary metaphysics (pp. 199–214). Bloomsbury.
Brenner, A. (2017). Simplicity as a criterion of theory choice in metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 174(11), 2687–2707. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0805-1
Bueno, O. (2009). Mathematical fictionalism. In O. Bueno & Ø. Linnebo (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mathematics (pp. 59–79). Palgrave Macmillan.
Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. OUP.
Chalmers, D. J. (2003). Consciousness and its place in nature. In S. P. Stich & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of mind (pp. 102–142). Blackwell.
Chalmers, D. J. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence (pp. 244–255). OUP.
Chalmers, D. J. (2010). The character of consciousness. OUP.
Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. MIT Press.
Dasgupta, S. (2014). The possibility of physicalism. The Journal of Philosophy, 111(9/10), 557–592. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20141119/1037
deRosset, L. (2010). Getting priority straight. Philosophical Studies, 149(1), 73–97. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9538-8
Dove, G. (2018). Redefining physicalism. Topoi, 37(3), 513–522. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9405-0
Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Harvard University Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown and Company.
Elpidorou, A. (2018). The character of physicalism. Topoi, 37(3), 435–455. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9488-2
Elpidorou, A., & Dove, G. (2018). Consciousness and physicalism: A defense of a research program. Routledge.
Forster, M., & Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45(1), 1–35. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/45.1.1
Francescotti, R. (2014). The problem of extras and the contingency of physicalism. Philosophical Explorations, 17(2), 241–254. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2013.787115
Gillett, C., & Loewer, B. (Eds.). (2001). Physicalism and its discontents. Cambridge University Press.
Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. OUP.
Hendry, R. F. (2017). Prospects for strong emergence in chemistry. In M. P. Paoletti & F. Orilia (Eds.), Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation (pp. 146–163). Routledge.
Hill, C. S. (1991). Sensations: A defense of type materialism. Cambridge University Press.
Horgan, T. (1993). From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world. Mind, 102(408), 555–586. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/102.408.555
Huemer, M. (2009). When is parsimony a virtue? Philosophical Quarterly, 59(235), 216–236. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2008.569.x
Jackson, F. (1993). Armchair metaphysics. In J. Hawthorne & M. Michael (Eds.), Philosophy in mind (pp. 23–42). Kluwer.
Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. OUP.
Jansson, L., & Tallant, J. (2017). Quantitative parsimony: Probably for the better. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(3), 781–803. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv064
Jaworski, W. (2016). Structure and the metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind-body problem. OUP.
Keas, M. N. (2018). Systematizing the theoretical virtues. Synthese, 195(6), 2761–2793. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1355-6
Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press.
Kriegel, U. (2013). The epistemological challenge of revisionary metaphysics. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(12), 1–30.
Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., & Tononi, G. (2016a). Neural correlates of consciousness: Progress and problems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17(5), 307–321. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.22
Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., & Tononi, G. (2016b). Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17(7), 450–461. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.44
Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In T. S. Kuhn (Ed.), The essential tension (pp. 310–339). University of Chicago.
Ladyman, J. (2012). Science, metaphysics and method. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 31–51. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9910-y
Lavazza, A., & Robinson, H. (2014). Contemporary dualism: A defense. Routledge.
Leuenberger, S. (2014). Grounding and necessity. Inquiry, 57(2), 151–174. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2013.855654
Levine, J., & Trogdon, K. (2009). The modal status of materialism. Philosophical Studies, 145(3), 351–362. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9235-z
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343–377. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408312341131
Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). MIT University Press.
Longino, H. E. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press.
Mayr, E. (1997). This is biology: The science of the living world. Harvard University Press.
McAllister, J. W. (1997). Phenomena and patterns in data sets. Erkenntnis, 47(1), 217–228. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005387021520
McLaughlin, B. P. (2001). In defense of new wave materialism: A response to Horgan and Tienson. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 319–330). Cambridge University Press.
McLaughlin, B. P. (2010). Consciousness, type physicalism, and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Issues, 20(1), 266–304. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1533-6077.2010.00192.x
McMullin, E. (2014). The virtues of a good theory. In M. Curd & S. Psillos (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 561–271). Routledge.
Melnyk, A. (2003). A physicalist manifesto: Thoroughly modern materialism. Cambridge University Press.
Melnyk, A. (2006). Realization and the formulation of physicalism. Philosophical Studies, 131(1), 127–155. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-5986-y
Melnyk, A. (2018). In defense of a realization formulation of physicalism. Topoi, 37(3), 483–493. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9404-1
Montero, B. G. (2013). Must physicalism imply the supervenience of the mental on the physical? The Journal of Philosophy, 110(2), 93–110. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil2013110240
Montero, B. G., & Brown, C. (2018). Making room for a this-worldly physicalism. Topoi, 37(3), 523–532. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9450-3
Ney, A. (2008a). Defining physicalism . Philosophy Compass, 3(5), 1033–1048. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00163.x
Ney, A. (2008b). Physicalism as an attitude. Philosophical Studies, 138(1), 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-0006-4
Nolan, D. (1997). Quantitative parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(3), 329–343. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/48.3.329
O’Conaill, D. (2018). Grounding, physicalism and necessity. Inquiry, 61(7), 713–730. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2017.1385524
Owen, M. (2018). Neural correlates of consciousness and the nature of the mind. In M. P. Guta (Ed.), Consciousness and the ontology of properties (pp. 241–260). Routledge.
Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. OUP.
Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as modeling: The handmaiden’s tale. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 1–29. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9906-7
Pereboom, D. (2011). Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. OUP.
Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge.
Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. S. (1970). The web of belief. Random House.
Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In R. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–136). OUP.
Russell, B. (1918/1956). The philosophy of logical atomism. Reprinted In R.C. Marsh (Ed.), Logic and Knowledge. London: Allen & Unwin (pp. 187–281).
Salmon, W. (1990). The appraisal of theories: Kuhn meets Bayes. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 325–332. https://doi.org/10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1990.2.193077
Schaffer, J. (2010). Monism: The priority of the whole. The Philosophical Review, 119(1), 31–76. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2009-025
Schaffer, J. (2015). What not to multiply without necessity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(4), 644–664. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2014.992447
Schindler, S. (2018). Theoretical virtues in science: Uncovering reality through theory. Cambridge University Press.
Scorzato, L. (2013). On the role of simplicity in science. Synthese, 190(1), 2867–2895. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0101-3
Seifert, V. A. (2020). The strong emergence of molecular structure. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 10(45), 1–25. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-020-00308-7
Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. OUP.
Skiles, A. (2015). Against grounding necessitarianism. Erkenntnis, 80(4), 717–751. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9669-y
Smart, J. J. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. The Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156. https://doi.org/10.2307/2182164
Sober, E. (1981). The principle of parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 32(1), 145–156. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/32.2.145
Sober, E. (1990). Explanations in biology: Let’s razor Ockham’s razor. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplementary, 27, 73–93. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246100005051
Sober, E. (2009). Parsimony arguments in science and philosophy—A test case for naturalismp. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 83(2), 117–155.
Sober, E. (2015). Ockham’s razors. Cambridge University Press.
Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. OUP.
Stoljar, D. (2010). Physicalism. Routledge.
Swinburne, R. (1997). Simplicity as evidence of truth. Marquette University Press.
Swinburne, R. (2001). Epistemic justification. OUP.
Trogdon, K. (2013). Grounding: Necessary or contingent? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 94(4), 465–485. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12009
van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. OUP.
van Fraassen, B. (2002). The empirical stance. Yale University Press.
Willard, M. B. (2014). Against simplicity. Philosophical Studies, 167(1), 165–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0228-1
Wilson, J. (2005). Supervenience-based formulations of physicalism. Noûs, 39(3), 426–459. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0029-4624.2005.00508.x
Wilson, J. (2006). On characterizing the physical. Philosophical Studies, 131(1), 61–99. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-5984-8
Wilson, J. (2010). What is Hume’s dictum, and why believe it? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(3), 595–637. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00342.x
Wilson, J. (2011). Non-reductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy. The Monist, 94(1), 121–154. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist20119417
Witmer, D. G. (2001). Sufficiency claims and physicalism: A formulation. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 57–73). Cambridge University Press.
Witmer, D. G. (2018). Physicality for physicalists. Topoi, 37(3), 457–472. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9415-y
Acknowledgements
For comments and feedback on various drafts of this work, I am grateful to Alfredo Tomasetta, David Papineau, Michele Di Francesco, Francesca Bellazzi, and Marco Facchin. Early versions of this paper were presented at the IUSS WIP webinars in Philosophy (July 2020) and at the MetaScience WIP webinars (University of Bristol, July 2020). I would like to thank the audience for their questions and suggestions. Finally, I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for providing extensive and helpful comments.
Funding
This work has been funded by the PRIN Project “The Mark of Mental” (MOM), 2017P9E9N, financed by the Italian Ministry of University and Research, active from 29/12/2019 to 28/12/2022.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interests
The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Zanotti, G. Physicalism and the burden of parsimony. Synthese 199, 11109–11132 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03281-7
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03281-7