The Teleological Ethics of Fakhr Al-Din Al-Razi - Ayman - Shihadeh
The Teleological Ethics of Fakhr Al-Din Al-Razi - Ayman - Shihadeh
ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY
THEOLOGY AND SCIENCE
Texts and Studies
EDITED BY
VOLUME LXIV
AYMAN SHIHADEH
BRILL
LEIDEN BOSTON
2006
ISSN 0169-8729
ISBN 90 04 14991 0
Copyright 2006 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands
Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill Academic Publishers,
Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written
permission from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal
use is granted by Brill provided that
the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright
Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910
Danvers MA 01923, USA.
Fees are subject to change.
contents
CONTENTS
Preface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
vii
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
General Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Al-Rzs Biography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
The Development of al-Rzs Thought and the
Chronology of his Works . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1
1
4
13
13
17
29
39
45
47
56
63
73
83
96
109
109
116
129
155
156
169
181
vi
contents
contents
vii
PREFACE
The present study aspires, first and foremost, to make a contribution
to two main areas of interest in Islamic intellectual history, namely
ethical philosophy and the thought of Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz. I hope
to have demonstrated that al-Rz is one of the most important
ethicists in Muslim history, and to have produced some stimuli for
further research on his thought, as he remains one of the most
influential, yet sorely understudied, medieval thinkers.
The present monograph is based, often remotely, on a doctoral
thesis that I submitted in 2002 to the faculty of Oriental Studies,
Oxford University, under the supervision of Professor Yahya Michot
and Dr Fritz Zimmermann. I would like to express my gratitude
to both my supervisors, from whom my research has benefited in
numerous ways. I am indebted to Professor Michot for more recent
exchanges of ideas, many of which are relevant to questions tackled
in this thoroughly revised version.
I would like also to extend my sincere thanks to Professor Wilferd
Madelung, Professor Hans Daiber and Dr Tony Street, who provided
me with valuable comments on this study, to Professor Yahya Ibn
Junaid and Dr Nizam Yaquby, who both assisted me in acquiring
copies of some manuscripts, and to Sobia Syyed for reading the
monograph and suggesting some corrections in style. Needless to
say, I alone am responsible for its present form.
Finally, I am truly grateful to the following institutions: to the
Muslim Academic Trust, Cambridge, for generously funding my
graduate study; to Oxford University for funding provided during
my doctoral study; to the British, Berlin State, Mar#ash-Najaf and
Princeton University Libraries, for facilitating access to manuscripts
of Rislat Dhamm ladhdht al-duny, allowing me to produce a critical
edition thereof; and to Brill for undertaking this publication.
viii
contents
introduction
INTRODUCTION
General Introduction
The first centuries of Islam witnessed the emergence of different
traditions of ethical thinking, within which several distinct ethical
theories were propounded. The most sophisticated philosophical
theories were developed within the two largely independent traditions of kalm and falsafa, which clashed at the level of ethics and
in other related areas, including metaphysics, cosmology, psychology
and epistemology.
The main ethical concern of the classical mutakallimn was to
investigate the nature of Gods justice and the goodness of His acts
generally, which they approached through analytical discussions of
ethical language, metaphysics and epistemology. Similar discussions,
likewise with an emphasis on action, can also be found in ul al-fiqh,
and concern the establishment of general normative principles for
human conduct. The falsifa, on the other hand, were chiefly, but by
no means solely, interested in the development of human character,
primarily by engendering virtues, which are essentially dispositions
internal to the individual.
The gap separating the two traditions was initially so wide that
many notions central to one tradition of ethical theory were completely
alien to the other, in which they would normally be dismissed in toto,
without engagement in any proper dialogue. Yet there then emerged
signs of increasing, and more positive, interaction between kalm
and falsafa, culminating in the efforts of al-Ghazl (d. 505/1111),
who was both a severe critic of the falsifa and deeply influenced by
them in many respects. A century later, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz was
to open the gates widely, allowing a more liberal exchange of ideas,
a synthesis even, between kalm and falsafa. This feature manifests
no less in his ethics than in other areas of his thought.
The present study is thus, at once, both a comprehensive analysis
of one major facet of al-Rzs thought, viz. his ethical theory, and an
exploration of the main trends and debates in its wider intellectual
background. It shows that he sets forth a sophisticated and original
ethical theory, which is both eclectic and highly consistent internally.
introduction
1 Ibn al-Akfn, Irshd, 401. The two other representative works that he lists are
Ibn Sns Rila f l-akhlq and Miskawayhs Al-Fawz al-aghar.
2 Contemporary ethical philosophy is normally divided into the sub-fields of
metaethics and normative ethics. The distinction is not universally accepted, primarily because the two fields are arguably not mutually exclusive. Metaethics, or
so-called second order ethics, seeks to understand the nature and justification
of ethical judgement. Normative, first order ethics denotes attempts to defend
or establish ethical judgements on specific types of human action, or norms and
principles to guide human action (cf. Sh. Kagan, Normative Ethics, esp. 16; articles
Analytic ethics, REP; Metaethics, EE).
3 These different types of ethical theory are defined p. 478 infra.
introduction
Rzs writings for several reasons. First of all, the classical mutakallimn focused on action exclusively, as they were concerned with
investigating how Gods acts relate to His creatures. Al-Rz, too,
discusses divine action, which he approaches on the basis of a thorough analysis of human action. Moreover, in developing his ethical
theory, he works within separate established traditions, each having
its own scope and ethos. He does not attempt to produce a synthesis
between the science of character and jurisprudence. Yet he does
provide some general guidelines on how the ethics of action and the
ethics of character should be viewed in relation to each other.
The starting point for this study will be al-Rzs ethics of action
(Chapter II), for which first we will need to examine his theory of
action, which is central to his metaethics (Chapter I). Since he starts
as a classical Ash#ar theologian with little interest in the examination
of character, his interest in action will have chronological precedence
in his intellectual career. Even in his later thought, his analysis of
action does not presuppose a theory of character (which normally
would give moral primacy to character over action), although it will
be complemented by such a theory. Chapter III will then examine his
theory of virtue, including his ethics of character and the influence
of his theory of virtue on his later theory of prophecy.
Chapter IV will focus on the epistle entitled Dhamm ladhdht alduny (Censure of the Pleasures of This World), which is published here
and studied for the first time (a critical edition can be found as an
Appendix). In this immensely interesting short text, which al-Rz
wrote towards the end of his life, he expresses pronounced moral
pessimism and intellectual scepticism. The background of this stance
in his writings more widely will also be explored.
The narrower theoretical themes covered in this study will be
introduced in their appropriate places in the following chapters.
First, however, we should provide a short biography of al-Rz and
a brief descriptive bibliography of his main writings that are cited
in this study.
introduction
Al-Rzs Biography4
4 Some of the main classical biographies of al-Rz are: Ibn Ab Uaybi#a, #Uyn,
3, 3445; al-Qif, Ikhbr, 1902; al-#Asqaln, Lisn, 4, 4269; Ab Shma, Dhayl,
68; Ibn Khallikn, Wafayt, 4, 24852; Ibn al-#Ibr, Trkh, 240; 254; Ibn al-S#,
Jmi#, 9, 3068; Ibn Kathr, Bidya, 13, 556; al-afad, Wf, 4, 24858; al-Dhahab,
Trkh, 43, 21123; al-Subk, abaqt, 8, 8196; al-Yfi#, Mir"t, 4, 711; al-Shahrazr, Nuzha, 2, 14450. See also: Muammad al-Zarkn, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, 855;
Georges Anawati, Tamhd, 193201; Elements; Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz in EI2;
John Cooper, al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din, REP; Yasin Ceylan, Theology, 113; Tony
Street, Life and Works; Jacques Jomier, Quranic Commentary.
5 Cf. al-Subk, abaqt, 3, 159 ff.; 7, 242; Ibn Khallikn, Wafayt, 4, 252.
6 Al-Rzs Ash#ar chain extends from his father, to Ab l-Qsim al-Anr,
to al-Juwayn, to Ab Isq al-Isfar"n, to Ab l-\asan al-Bhil, to al-Ash#ar
(Tal al-aqq, 52; cf. al-Yfi#, Mir"t, 4, 11). He also presents his Shfi# juristic
chain, starting with his father.
7 Ibn Ab Uaybi#a, #Uyn, 3, 34.
8 E.g. Munart, 7; Malib, 7, 38891. On his travels, see J. Jomier, Quranic
Commentary, passim.
introduction
introduction
their author. Most, including all the important ones, are in Arabic;
some are in Persian.
The present study uses the most comprehensive selection of alRzs works to date; several are used for the first time. This has
allowed a more accurate understanding of the complex developments
that took place in his thought, which are often subtle, but sometimes
striking. Some of his earliest and latest works give the impression
of being written by very different authors (yet they are his, without
doubt). To give one curious example, while in the early Ishra, Ab
l-#Al" al-Ma#arr is cursed for his heresy, he is referred to appreciatively in the late Tafsr and Malib as the philosopher-poet (akm
al-shu#ar"). It is an all too familiar mistake for studies to cite a view
presented in one or two of al-Rzs books as being simply his view,
when in fact contrasting views may be readily found in his other,
or later, published works.
Moreover, as was the practice of many other authors, al-Rz
will often treat a problem thoroughly in one book, and will then
refer to it in passing in later books, sometimes without mention of
the earlier discussion. In one book, he writes that he will avoid discussing topics that have been discussed elsewhere.14 It is, therefore,
not uncommon for readers of a given work by al-Rz, pre-modern
and modern alike, to conclude that he fails to address a particular
problem, when in fact the author himself is satisfied in having done
so elsewhere.
At this stage, we are able to determine the exact dating of some
of al-Rzs works and to estimate the general, relative chronology
of others. Some texts remain very difficult to date, except sometimes
very tentatively. Internal evidence of dates, such as references made
to other works, may often mislead, since some works underwent
revision by their author years after they were first written. Thus,
e.g. we find references in the Mabith to Shar Kulliyyt al-Qnn and
vice versa, which leads us to conclude either that both were written
in the same period, or that references in at least one of them were
inserted in a later revision.
Al-Rzs earliest works are strictly classical Ash#ar in style and
content.15 This is most evident in Ul al-n and, to a slightly lesser
14
introduction
degree, the Ishra. In the later Nihyat al-#uql, he introduces Aristotelian logic into kalm, but still proclaims, in line with classical
Ash#arism, that the purpose of his theological enquiry is to defend
the orthodox creed. Later, he wholeheartedly embraces the growing
eclecticism of his milieu, and starts to write works on falsafa, logic,
medicine and the occult. At this stage, he writes the Mabith and
the Mulakhkha, which he describes as falsaf, or ikm, works, in
contrast to his kalm works. He then returns to writing in the latter
genre, gradually synthesising kalm and falsafa.16
The following is a chronological list, with brief descriptions, of
some of the most important works used in the present study. Most of
the internal evidence for the dating has been omitted; a systematic
evaluation thereof will go well beyond the scope of this bibliographic
introduction.
[Kitb f Ul al-dn, #aq"id ahl al-sunna]. The original title of this
unpublished volume is uncertain; hence, it will be referred to as Ul
al-dn.17 Given its classical Ash#ar content and approach, it appears
to be the earliest known theological book authored by al-Rz. He
demonstrates great familiarity with the works of al-Ash#ar (d. 324/
936) and the main proponents of his school, to whom he refers as
our masters (a"immatun), including al-Bqilln (d. 403/1013), his
student Ab Ja#far al-Simnn (d. 444/1052), Ab Isq al-Isfar"n
(d. 418/1027) and al-Juwayn (d. 478/1085).
Al-Ishra f #ilm al-kalm.18 This book represents al-Rzs earliest,
highly Ash#ar stage, but is slightly later than Ul al-dn.19
Al-Mal f #ilm al-ul. Completed in 576/1180,20 this is al-Rzs
most important, and highly influential, work on ul al-fiqh.
Nihyat al-#uql f diryat al-ul. Still unpublished, this large kalm
16
introduction
21
introduction
27 Mentioned in Muaal, 202. Also, both the Mabith and the Mulakhkha are
mentioned in Shar al-Ishrt, 1, 153. It was taught in Bukhara in 582/1186 (see
following note).
28 The date is mentioned in Munart, 32. The Mabith, the Mulakhkha and
Shar al-Ishrt, are mentioned in Munart, 60.
29 Cf. Shihadeh, From al-Ghazl to al-Rz, 1712.
30 The Tafsr is mentioned in Arba#n, 423. This suggests that al-Rz wrote the
Arba#n around 595600/11991204, after starting the Tafsr.
31 Ktib elebi, Kashf al-unn, 1, 94.
32 Manqib, 538.
33 Mentioned in Tafsr, 15, 55; 22, 13.
10
introduction
introduction
11
38 Dates are given at the end of each book. Book 3 is not dated in the printed
edition, yet the authors colophon in MS Chester Beatty Ar 3114 (fol. 147a) dates
it to 605/1208.
39 The Malib is mentioned in Shar #Uyn al-ikma, 3, 100. The discussion
referred to appears in book 7 of the Malib.
12
introduction
13
CHAPTER ONE
1
2
Ul al-dn, fol. 220. Cf. Harry Wolfson, Philosophy of the Kalam, 522 ff.
Cf. passage from the Mal, p. 100 infra.
14
chapter one
For Ash#ars, only one, specific act could follow from a specific
instance of power. The accident of the power to move my arm will
exist in my arm at the time of motion and will relate to that specific
3 Ul al-dn, fol. 231. On the doctrine of acquisition, see Daniel Gimaret, Thories
de lacte humain, 69 ff.
4 Ul al-dn, fol. 222; 225.
5 Muaal, 253.
6 Ul al-dn, fol. 227.
15
16
chapter one
11
17
17
18
18
chapter one
19
20
21
22
23
19
Rather, it may exist continuously, before, during and after the act,
though it acts as a cause only when it combines with motivation.
The act, therefore, is produced by the combination of power and
motivation, rather than the mere presence of power. When this combination occurs a complete cause (mu"aththir tmm) emerges, which
produces the effect at exactly the same instant.24 Al-Rz concludes
that if capability denotes power, it will indeed exist before action;
however, if it denotes the combination of power and motive, it will
be simultaneous with (#inda) action. As such, he affirms the traditional
Ash#ar formula, Capability and action occur simultaneously.
Al-Rzs analysis of human action is in agreement with the classical
Ash#ar stance with respect to its atomism and occasionalism, though,
essentially, it constitutes a very different theory. On the other hand, it
is mainly on account of its atomism and occasionalism that al-Rzs
analysis of action contrasts with that of Ibn Sn, with which it is
otherwise in general agreement. In the Mabith, Ibn Sn, for whom
time is a continuum, is cited criticising those who claim that power
is simultaneous with action: they will have to accept that someone
who is seated is incapable of standing up (i.e. it is not possible, in his
constitution, for him to stand up), unless he does stand up; so how
could he stand up!25 In response, al-Rz argues that potentiality
(quwwa) is the principle of change and exists simultaneously with the
change it effects, whereas power is only a constituent of potentiality
and exists before the act. He adds, If it is possible to interpret the
claims of those people in the way we explain, what need is there to
attack them and to deride their claims!26 Again, however, al-Rz
must be aware that he does not merely introduce an interpretation
of the Ash#ar claim, but a fundamentally different theory.
24
Ma#lim, 83.
Ibn Sn (Shif", Ilhiyyt, 1, 1767) attributes this view to some ancients,
including Ghrqw (sic.) and some people who came very long after him, probably in reference to Ash#ars. The reference to the 4th3rd century BC Megarian
school (Ghrqn) is taken from Aristotles Metaphysics (IX.3). Ibn Rushd (Tafsr
m ba#d al-ab#a, 2, 11246) comments: Nowadays, among [the followers of] our
religion, this view is upheld by the Ash#ars, and it is a view that contradicts human
nature, with respect to both beliefs and acts. (See Megarian School, REP).
26 Mabith, 1, 3823; cf. Mulakhkha, fol. 159b160a; Ibn Sn, Shif", Ilhiyyt,
1, 1767.
25
20
chapter one
Motivation
According to al-Rz, the production of human action requires the
combination of power and a preponderator (murajji); power, on its
own, is passive potentiality that will produce an effect only when
prompted by an external factor.27 Since human acts are contingent, and since a nonexistent contingent will require a cause for
its existence to preponderate (tarajjaa) over its non-existence, the
occurrence of the act will be inconceivable without such a cause,
and necessitated by it. Al-Rz rejects the view that the cause will
merely make acting more probable (awl) than omission; for the two
probabilities will be either equivalent, in which case no change will
occur, or not equivalent, in which case the preponderant possibility
will prevail.28 As soon as acting preponderates, the act will occur
instantly.29 Al-Rz summarises the argument in the Mulakhkha:
On that the Acts of Servants are [Subject to] Divine Determination. Human
capability either has the potentiality to produce opposite [acts], or not.
The latter [view] amounts to the affirmation of compulsion (jabr).
In the former [view], the production of one of the two [possible]
objects of power (maqdr) from [human capacity], to the exclusion of
the other, will either depend on a preponderator, or not. [If not,] it
would follow that one of the two possible alternatives preponderates
over the other without a preponderator.
[If acting depends on a preponderator,] that preponderator will be
produced by either the servant (and the above disjunction will re-apply),
or God. Then, the production of that effect, when that preponderator occurs, is either necessary, or not. The latter is inconceivable; for
otherwise [the effect] would leave the state of equivalence, without
reaching the state of necessitationwhich we have refuted elsewhere.
The former amounts to compulsion.30
Al-Rz repeatedly argues that to deny the principle of preponderation will be tantamount to denying the existence of the Creator,
which is proven mainly on the basis of this principle.31
The preponderator in question is identified as will (irda, mash"a),
which acts as a decisive will (irda jzima), or inclination (mayl jzim),
27
28
29
30
31
21
since it will necessitate its effect.32 This will originates from a final
cause within the agent, which is his intention, or objective. Al-Rz
writes, commenting on Ibn Sn:
How excellent is the Shaykhs saying that the final cause is an active
cause for the causality of the active cause (al-#illa al-gh"iyya #illa f#iliyya
li-#illiyyat al-#illa al-f#iliyya)! For the living being may be able to move
right or left. Therefore, before the preponderance of one over the
other, it will be an agent in potentiality. If it imagines benefit in either
of the two movements, that imagination will become an efficient cause
for that potentiality becoming an actual cause for one of the two
movements.33
32
22
chapter one
38
39
40
41
Malib,
Malib,
Malib,
Malib,
3,
3,
3,
3,
10.
178.
18.
1920.
23
Seeking pleasure and avoiding pain are the two simple, primal instincts
which underlie all human motivation.
These two primal instincts constitute the rudimentary elements
for the calculations involved in more complex motives, as follows.
Harm in general, which is avoided in itself, is of three main types:
(a) real harm, which is the immediate experience of pain, (b) the
negation of benefit, and (c) the negation of what prevents harm (daf #
dfi# al-arar). Benefit in general, which is sought for its own sake, is
42
43
44
24
chapter one
also of three types: (a) real benefit, which is the immediate experience of pleasure, (b) the prevention of harm, and (c) the prevention
of what impedes benefit. Some of these constitute generally stronger
motives than others; e.g. expecting harm is a stronger motive than
expecting the negation of an equal benefit. Moreover, overall motives
vary in strength according to whether they are based on knowledge,
conviction or presumption.45
The agents mind weighs the various advantages and disadvantages
it conceives within an act. If the agent then believes that the act will
be purely advantageous, he will be compellingly motivated (mulja")
to perform it, and will perform it by necessity. If he finds it purely
disadvantageous, he will omit it.46 However, if he believes that the
act involves both advantageous and disadvantageous aspects, he
will be compellingly motivated to perform or omit it, according to
which of the two choices he conceives to be preponderant. If both
are equal, he will abstain from acting (tawaqquf ).47
All the motives and deterrents that influence the agent at a given
situation will add up and subtract in an often complex calculation
within the agents mind. Equal conflicting motivational quantities
will, as it were, cancel each other out, leaving, as their end product,
only a single quantity that effects action. Al-Rz himself uses mathematical language to describe this process; he writes that if equivalent
opposed motives cancel each other out, the remaining quantity
[lit. number (#adad z"id)] will remain as a pure (khli) motive for
action.48 Such calculative processes often involve multiple stages.
Suppose that an agent, in a given situation, has to choose between
more than one course of action, when he expects that each would
45
Malib, 3, 23 ff.
Malib, 3, 25. Al-Rzs use of the term compelling motivation (ilj") comes
directly from its use by Mu#tazils. #Abd al-Jabbr seems to borrow the term from
Ab Hshim al-Jubb", to denote the particular case of the intentional act, which
the agent finds himself virtually forced to choose (Mughn, 11, 395; 12, 128; cf.
Richard Frank, The Autonomy of the Human Agent in the Teaching of #Abd
al-@abbr, 340; D. Gimaret, Thories de lacte humain, 56 ff.). According to #Abd
al-Jabbr, when the agent is subject to only one sufficiently strong motive, it will
be impossible for him to act in any other way; as such, he will be compellingly
motivated. Mu#tazils, therefore, viewed compelling motivation as an extreme case,
unrepresentative of human action in general. Al-Rz generalises it to include all
human action.
47 Malib, 3, 26; Jabr, 2233.
48 Malib, 3, 26.
46
25
49
26
chapter one
makes the occurrence of an act more likely than others, but does not
necessarily determine it.
Al-Rz points out a crucial difference between the theories of
action of Ibn al-Malim and his master Ab l-\usayn: the latter
holds that the act depends (mawqf ) on the motive, whereas the
former holds that the motive does not necessitate the act, but makes
it more likely to occur.55 However, it seems that Ab l-\usayn does
not state explicitly that the motive necessitates the act, as al-Rz
criticises him for shying away from admitting this obvious implication to his position. One may wonder here whether there was indeed
such a disagreement between Ab l-\usayn and Ibn al-Malim,
as al-Rz claims.56 In his work al-Mu#tamad f ul al-dn, Ibn alMalim does not seem to refer to this point of divergence with
Ab l-\usayn; yet he does point out another relevant disagreement
with him of which al-Rz too is aware, viz. that Ab l-\usayn
affirms the role of will in human action. Will, according to him, is
produced by motives; for when man knows that a thing contains a
preponderant benefit, he will find that his self seeks it, and he will
find this seeking (alab) to be as though produced by this knowledge
and following from it.57 The immediate motive for action becomes
will, or inclination in the heart (mayl al-qalb).58 Therefore, since
Ab l-\usayn maintains that action presupposes the presence of
motivation and that the presence of a single motive in the agent
at a given moment will compel him to act in accordance with it, it
should follow (though Ab l-\usayn appears not to admit this) that
the emergence of a single will from multiple partial motives will
constitute a decisive will. Al-Rz argues that Ab l-\usayn will
have to admit that motivation necessitates action. As such, he may
appear justified in accusing him of inconsistency.59
In the Malib, al-Rz includes a section on this view, which he
attributes to Ab l-\usayn, entitled On whether the production of
55
27
60
28
chapter one
29
constituting a compelling motive. People call one who is generally hesitant and undecided dh badawt, since, at one moment, a
certain act will seem (bad) to him to be of preponderant benefit,
while, at another moment, he will conceive another act to be so; this
indecision may be due to his nature. Also, the agent may perceive
something that may remind him of, or invoke in him, a certain
knowledge or conviction that motivates him, whereas perceiving
something else, one moment later, may invoke a different conviction
in his mind.73 Considerations of benefit and harm are many and
virtually countless; the greater the minds reckoning of them, the
greater the perplexity and confusion.74
Destiny
Al-Rz presents various arguments against Mu#tazil claims of free
human choice, one of the most important of which goes as follows.
The combination of power and motivation either necessitates, or
does not necessitate, the act. The former possibility will lead to a
type of determinism (jabr), since the agents motives cannot rely
on other motives ad infinitum, but should ultimately originate from
motives that God creates. Al-Rz then continues with an argument
ad hominem, viz. that the latter possibility will entail that when power
and motivation combine, action may or may not follow. In other
words, if we imagine that a given situation involving an agent, who
has to make a choice, is repeated a number of absolutely identical
times, the choice that the agent makes will follow sometimes, but
not at all times; i.e. it will occur randomly, by pure chance and
for no reason. This would result in another type of determinism,
whereby human action is determined by pure chance.75
Having demonstrated that the combination of motivation and
power determines the act, al-Rz discusses the only preceding stage
in the production of human action, viz. the emergence of motivation
from cognitive states. By arguing that both stages are deterministic,
he proves that human action as a whole is determined. He writes:
73
74
75
Jabr, 43.
Malib, 3, 28.
Jabr, 134.
30
chapter one
Man finds in himself that unless he wants to act he will not be able to
act, and unless he wills to abstain he will not be able to abstain. That
will is not due to another will; for, otherwise, this would entail infinite
regress. It is thus certain that those wills go back to a necessary will
that occurs in the heart without will. And if that decisive will occurs
in the heart, the occurrence of the act will undoubtedly be necessary.
Therefore, neither the occurrence of will in the heart is of the persons
[own doing], nor is the occurrence of the act after the occurrence of
will in his heart of the persons [own doing]. All is thus from God.
And man is compelled under the guise of a voluntary agent.76
76
31
The main internal ones are: (a) variations in the essences of human
souls;80 (b) variations in temperance; and (c) physiognomic variations. The three main external factors are: (d) habituation; (e) the
expectation of certain benefits or harms from adhering to certain
beliefs; and (f) theoretical training. These six factors will determine
the agents character, while accidental (ittifq) external circumstances,
perceived through the senses, will act as more direct factors in the
production of motives.81 All these are factors that the agent will
have no control over.
In Kitb al-Jabr, we find a lengthy section containing proofs for
the view that man has no power whatsoever over the contents of his
knowledge.82 Even religious belief and disbelief are products, not of
the agents choice, but purely of Gods creative power. A number
of arguments are advanced.
It is first argued that all acquired (muktasab) knowledge will depend
on self-evident (badh) knowledge that the mind knows immediately
and spontaneously, not by choice. So, at a given moment, all that
is necessary for self-evident knowledge to entail acquired knowledge either exists within the agent, or does not exist. If it exists,
that acquired knowledge will come into being immediately, not by
choice. If not all that is necessary exists, something will still be
needed for the appearance of acquired knowledge. That something
cannot be self-evident knowledge (which is already assumed). Nor
can it be acquired knowledge, in the case of the first bit of acquired
knowledge. Al-Rz seems to imply that it can only be divine, rather
than human, will (since an agents will depends on his knowledge). It
follows, he concludes, that self-evident knowledge is not produced by
human will, nor are the first, second and following bits of acquired
knowledge.
Al-Rzs second proof is as follows. Knowledge is either conception (taawwur) or assertion (tadq), the former being apprehension
(idrk) without judgement (ukm), and the latter being, according to
al-Rz, apprehension with a judgement of fact. He first argues that
conceptions are not acquired. For if I try to acquire a conception, I
will either have awareness (shu#r) of the essence to be conceptualised,
80
81
82
32
chapter one
83
84
85
Jabr, 105.
Jabr, 1057.
Jabr, 108.
33
86
87
246.
88 Jabr, 26; cf. p. 28 supra. This same point is made by Ibn Sn; cf. S. al-Budr,
Naariyyat Ibn Sn f l-fi#l, 67.
89 Cf. Lawmi#, 360; Malib, 7, 329. Ibn Sn (Ta#lqt, 523) gives a similar
distinction between natural causes and voluntary ones, and adds that human acts
will not be voluntary in reality.
34
chapter one
35
duces into his theory of action appears to be one of the places where
his synthesis between falsafa and kalm proves most difficult,93 especially that he had to face well-established criticisms of falsafa. However, in the Malib, his last major work, he solves this problem,
alongside other problems relating to divine action, by adopting a
highly unusual stance, as follows.
In all works earlier than the Malib, al-Rz affirms the common
Sunni doctrine that will is a real attribute of divine essence that is
distinct from the attributes of knowledge and power; and he locates
divine choice (ikhtiyr) in this attribute.94 Thus, the attribute of will
consists of both the ability to choose one of two possible options
freely and the actual choices themselves. Al-Rz rejects the views
of some Mu#tazils on divine will, such as the Baghdds95 and Ab
l-\usayn l-Bar, who argues that, unlike human will, which is real
and produced by motives, divine will refers to Gods motives only,
which are included in His knowledge.96
However, al-Rz defines will, in animate beings (i.e. in the
observable), in terms of the inclination (mayl) that follows naturally
from motives, and he thereby excludes the notion of choice from
it. As such, irda, as the mere natural product of motives, becomes
decisive (jzima), just as inclination is decisive (mayl jzim), and totally
contrary to free choice. Therefore, if our knowledge of the divine
attribute of will depends on qiys, whereby the unobservable is judged
in accordance with the observable, a clear implication will follow.
Al-Rz arrives at this in a section on the nature of will (aqqat alirda), in his discussion of divine attributes:
All we know in the meaning of will and aversion (karhiya) is the
inclination of the natural disposition (ab#) to attaining benefits and
its inclination to avoiding harms. Since this is inconceivable in relation to God, it will be inconceivable to affirm the notions of will and
aversion to Him.97
93
36
chapter one
God is not compellingly motivated (and, thereby, not a necessitating cause) because He does not have will, i.e. natural inclination
(mayl), which follows from motivation. As we will see in the next
chapter, al-Rz also maintains that Gods acts are not motivated.
Therefore, while Ab l-\usayn considers divine will to refer to
nothing but Gods motives, al-Rz denies that God has either will
or motivation.
This highly unorthodox later position brings al-Rz into conflict
with mainstream Sunni theology, which affirms a real and distinct
divine attribute of will.98 Yet it is an implication of his theory of action
that he accepts sincerely, not simply for dialectical consumption to
address what, he admits, is a strong Mu#tazil argument. Strangely,
by his denial of the divine attribute of will, al-Rz does not seem
to locate divine choice in any other attribute, though he still affirms
that God is a voluntary agent.
Having reached a consistent position as regards human and
divine action, the charge of inconsistency he directs at Ab l-\usayn
becomes more tenable:
Ab l-\usayn was confused on [whether the production of action by
power depends on motivation]. Whenever he discourses with the falsifa
on their saying, Why did God single out a specific time, rather than
a preceding or succeeding one, to create the world? he says, Action
does not depend on motivation. Whenever he discourses with his
companions on all other matters, he says, Action depends on motivation, and preponderation without a preponderator is self-evidently
inconceivable.99
98
Ibn Taymiyya (Majm#, 13, 128; cf. 6, 245) writes, Al-Rz discusses the
problem of will in al-Malib al-#$liya, and chooses to deny [Gods] will. For he
was unable to answer the argument of the falsifa using the principles of his companions of Jahms and Mu#tazils, so he ran off to their side! Ibn Taymiyya also
dedicates a work to refuting this position put forward in the Malib (Ibn #Abd
al-Hd, #Uqd, 51).
99 Jabr, 12. In a later episode of this debate, Ibn Taymiyya (Minhj, 1, 111; cf.
Dar", 1, 326) adopts this argument, but directs it at al-Rz:
Whenever ... al-Rz and his followers debate with Mu#tazils on matters of
destiny, they ... hold that one of the objects of the capacity of the voluntary
agent can preponderate only by a complete preponderator. Whenever they
debate with the falsifa on the questions of the creation of the world, the
affirmation of Gods choice and the refutation of [their notion of God being]
a necessitating cause, they follow the route of Mu#tazils and Jahms in saying
that one of the objects of the capacity of the voluntary agent may preponderate over the other without a preponderator.
37
Yet Ibn Taymiyya himself then relies on arguments similar to al-Rzs in criticising
the position of Mu#tazils and Qadars on human free choice (Dar", 1, 329).
100 Arba#n, 3434; Muaal, 471; Ma#lim, 8990; Jabr, 4665.
101 See, e.g., Jabr, 341, where he speaks of mas"alat al-d# wa-mas"alat al-#ilm.
102 Muaal, 471.
103 Jabr, 113389. Al-Rz clarifies his general methodology in dealing with
scriptural evidence, and he is clear about their being generally less conclusive than
rational evidence (Jabr, 113118). To the objection that the Qur"n contains verses
that support both the view of the determination of acts and that of free choice, he
states that Gods speech includes both explicit truth (aqqa) and metaphor (majz),
and one should try to see the truth that lies behind the latter by interpretation
(ta"wl) (Jabr, 1323).
104 Lawmi#, 242; Tafsr, 24, 179; Malib, 3, 60; Jabr, 25; 258; Manqib, 122; cf.
Ibn Sn, Ta#lqt, 51; 53. Al-Rz (Tafsr, 15, 64) also quotes this from a defence
of predeterminism by al-Ghazl (Iy", 4, 235).
105 Jabr, 43; Mabith, 2, 517; Mal, 1/2, 389. Cf. al-Ghzal (Iy", 4, 6): All is
from God. Indeed even choice is from God. Man is compelled in the choosing that
he has (muarr f l-ikhtiyr alladh lahu). Al-Rzs statements left a strong impact on
some later authors (e.g. al-Ifahn, Kshif, 4, 356; al-Taftazn, Shar, 4, 263).
106 Jabr, 41.
107 Respectively: Jabr, 43; Mabith, 2, 217; Khalq, fol. 46a.
38
chapter one
108
39
113
114
Tafsr, 2, 523.
Mulakhkha, fol. 1a.
40
chapter one
41
not lead to the same problems that arise in the Ash#ar model of
action.
Hence, in the late Kitb al-Jabr, he cites a Mu#tazil argument
from Qur"nic evidence for the view that man produces his acts
and against the doctrine of acquisition. The Mu#tazila conclude, he
notes, that bringing the word acquisition into this subject is pure
falsification (ma al-tazwr). He replies, referring to the contrary
view that God creates and determines all events:
It is necessary to harmonise between the two positions. We say: The
combination of power and motivation effects (mu"aththir) the act; and
the creator of this combination is God, exalted. Since this combination
implies (mustalzim) the occurrence of the act, the attribution [of acts to
human agents] will be real. Since this combination necessitates (mjib)
the occurrence of these acts, it becomes true that all is by Gods decree
and determination. In this way, the contradiction between rational
evidence and this Qur"nic evidence disappears. Know that this is true
according to my position in particular, as I hold that the combination
of power and motivation implies the act. As for one who does not hold
this, it will be hard for him to accept these verses.123
Far from defending the Ash#ar position, al-Rz presents his position
as a superior alternative.
Yet, crucially, he seems to contend, in this last passage, that the
act is caused by the combination of power and motivation, rather
than by the agency of God directly. This would come into serious conflict with classical Ash#arism, which affirms, not only Gods
absolute determination of all beings, but also that He creates them
all directly: they sought to affirm both qa" and khalq. This begs
the question: does al-Rz, in the relatively late Kitb al-Jabr, only
affirm qa"?
Though he rarely discusses the problem of natural causality directly,
there are indications in these later works that al-Rz indeed departs
with the standard classical Ash#ar position on this question. For
instance, in the course of his commentary on Qur. 2:22, [God]
sent down rain from the heavens and brought forth therewith fruits
for your sustenance, he posits the question of whether God creates
fruits following rain by sustaining the habitual order of created things,
123
Jabr, 3001.
42
chapter one
124
Tafsr, 2, 110.
Jabr, 11. Cf. Ibn Sn, Najt, 136 ff.
126 E.g. Kamliyya (Ar.), 63; (Per.), 74. On Ibn Sns notion of the cosmogonic
role of the Active Intellect, cf. Herbert Davidson, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on
Intellect, 74 ff.
127 Jabr, 112.
125
43
the Mabith, al-Rz maintains that all created beings are brought into
being directly by God; yet, whereas some things can be existentiated
only by virtue of being possible, others will require the presence of
some preparing (mu#idd) factors.128 He stresses, however, that though
this is the manner in which effects are produced ordinarily, it does
not contradict Gods voluntary agency, since He is in principle able
to suspend natural order and to create effects without any preparing
causes, as, for instance, in the case of prophetic miracles.
Later than Kitb al-Jabr, in the Malib, al-Rz summarises his
position as follows:
On Explaining How the Servant is an Agent. We hold that the combination
of power and a specific motive implies (mustalzim) the occurrence of the
act. Our saying implies refers to a denominator that is common (qadr
mushtarak) to that combination being a preparing cause (sabab mu#idd)
for the occurrence of that act and its being an efficient cause (sabab
mu"aththir) for it. Since the existentiator129 of power and motivation
is God, exalted, and since it has been proven that their combination
implies the occurrence of the act, the servant will become a real agent
(f#il f l-aqqa); for the effecter of that act is his power and motivation.
All mans acts will thus occur according to Gods decree. Not as much
as an atom in the heavens or the earth will escape the chain of Gods
decree and predestination (silsilat qa" Allh wa-qadarih). The demonstration for this is that it has been proven that the preponderance of
one of two alternatives depends on the preponderator; and it has been
proven that that preponderator is [produced] by Gods agency.130
128
129
130
Mabith, 2, 5078.
Reading mjid instead of muwajjih.
Malib, 3, 73.
44
chapter one
45
CHAPTER TWO
46
chapter two
47
objective notion of the perfection of human nature (cf. Th. Hurka, Perfectionism;
Perfectionism, REP and EE).
(2) Deontological theories treat certain acts as good or bad, or as duties, regardless to some extent of their consequences (cf. Deontological Ethics, REP). They
have further subdivisions, including the following two:
(a) Ethical realism, or objectivism, treats ethical value as intrinsic to acts, thus
neither willed by agents, nor reducible to non-rational inclinations (cf. D. Brink,
Moral Realism; Moral Realism, REP and EE).
(b) Divine command ethics rest on the single, basic non-teleological principle
that an act is good or bad if and only if, and because, it is commanded or prohibited by God. Often, good and bad are said to mean, respectively, commanded
or prohibited (W. Frankena, Ethics, 28; cf. Voluntarism, REP; P. Rooney, Divine
Command Morality). However, if a divine command theory bases obligation on afterlife
consequences of acts, it will become fundamentally a teleological theory.
6 On the Mu#tazil refutation of Ash#ar voluntarism, see George Hourani, Islamic
Rationalism, 97 ff.; #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 102.
7 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 58. Al-Rz sums the core Mu#tazil ethical position,
as do many of their other critics, by reference to both their realist and epistemological
stances: Mu#tazils claim [a] that the bad is bad by virtue of something that relates
to it (amr #"id ilayh), and [b] that reason either knows that aspect autonomously
(istaqalla bi-ma#rifatih) or not (Nihya, fol. 193b).
8 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 18.
9 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 63.
48
chapter two
or the acts consequences.10 Hence, lying and killing are bad and
prohibited absolutely, whatever their circumstances.
The Baran Mu#tazila (the later and more widespread branch
of Mu#tazilism) reject this ethical absolutism.11 They maintain that
ethical judgement depends on the aspects (wajh) upon which acts are
performed. Inflicting pain, for instance, is bad only within certain
sets of circumstances, e.g. that it neither leads to a greater benefit,
nor averts a greater harm.12
In Mu#tazil ethics, the fundamental ethical principles are universal,
in that they are immutable and apply equally to all agents, including
humans and God. Hence, Mu#tazils consider God to have certain
obligations towards humans, which stem from His essential justice,
wisdom, beneficence (isn), truthfulness, etc. According to #Abd alJabbr, although God is a voluntary agent and has the power to perform both good and bad acts, it is inconceivable for Him to perform
the latter, since He will have knowledge of their intrinsic badness.13
God, thus, acts for the wellbeing, or advantage, (al, malaa) of
humans, never in contradiction to it. The Baghdd Mu#tazila took
the more radical view that God is obligated to do what is most
advantageous (ala) to humans in some respects.
As in all deontological theories, account has to be made of the
consequences of some forms of action. In the ethics of the Barans,
this appears, for instance, in their theory of aspects, which often
takes account of considerations of benefit and harm that follow from
acts, though they maintain that an acts ethical value remains ultimately intrinsic. Wrongdoing (ulm) involves, among other aspects, the
delivery of harm to another, while beneficence involves the delivery
of benefit. Yet their respective badness and goodness are somehow
intrinsic, and not due to their actual consequences, which are often
subjective.
Benefit (naf #) and advantage (al) are defined in terms of sensual
pleasure (ladhdha) and joy (surr), whereas harm (arar) and disadvantage ( fasd) are defined in terms of pain (alam) and grief (ghamm).14
These constitute the primary elements for more complex calcula-
10
11
12
13
14
49
15 Nihya, fol. 194b195a. Ibn al-Malims Kitb al-\udd, apparently nonextant, is also mentioned in another work of his, the F"iq (cf. editorial intro. to
his Mu#tamad, iv).
16 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 14, 35.
17 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 14, 36.
50
chapter two
Also, the lexical meaning of justice is balance (i#tidl) and equilibrium (istiw") in everything, i.e. that there be neither excess nor
18
19
51
remissness in it. Ab Isq al-Isfar"n goes even further by interpreting good and bad in the same manner:
Justice is to put things in their appropriate places, and this is the
fundamental sense of goodness (usn); injustice is to put things in
other than their appropriate places, and this is the fundamental sense
of badness (qub).20
20
From: R. Frank, Creation and the Cosmic System, 64, with some modification.
Al-Ghazl writes, The Wise (\akm) means the knower of the realities
of things and the one capable of creating them perfectly according to His will
(Qudsiyya, 90; cf. Iqtid, 1656; Ibn Frak, Mujarrad, 967).
22 Ibn Frak, Mujarrad, 1412; cf. 967.
23 Ibn Frak, Mujarrad, 96.
21
52
chapter two
24 Cf. Ibn Frak (quoting al-Ash#ar), Mujarrad, 142; al-Juwayn, Nimiyya, 27;
al-Ghazl, Iqtid, 171; Mustaf, 1, 59.
25 Ibn Frak, Mujarrad, 127.
26 Al-Kiy al-Harrs, Ul al-Dn, fol. 200b; cf. 201b.
53
27
28
29
30
54
chapter two
55
no meaning for its badness other than its contradicting his purpose.
What neither contradicts nor agrees [with his purpose] is called vain
(#abath), i.e. that there is no benefit ( f"ida) in it at all.33
56
chapter two
The third sense is clearly related to the first two. Al-Ghazl then
goes on to give the Ash#ar definition of wisdom, in terms of the
perfection of knowledge and action.
The influence of al-Ghazls rudimentary consequentialism on
later mainstream kalm was apparently limited. We find classical
Ash#ar voluntarism being defended by al-Shahrastn, who also
rejects the theory of motivation entirely.38 This same stance appears
also in al-Rzs earliest kalm work, Ul al-dn, where he writes:
Nothing is good in itself or its species. Indeed, judgements (viz. goodness, badness, obligation, prohibition, recommendation (nadb), reprehensibility (karhiya) and permissibility) rely on the statements of the
Lawgiver. Good is what Revealed Law presents praise for one who
does it, and bad is what Revealed Law presents blame for one who
does it. ... Goodness is the same as the Laws presentation of praise
for one who does [an act].39
Ethical Value
Whereas al-Rzs earliest known kalm work, Ul al-dn, presents a
classical Ash#ar theory of value, we encounter a more sophisticated
ethical theory in his later works. In the Muaal, he defines the
central value terms as follows:
Goodness (usn) and badness (qub) may be intended to refer to [a]
agreeability (mul"ama) and disagreeability (munfara) to disposition (ab#),
and to [b] something being an attribute of perfection or imperfection.
In these two senses, they are rational (#aql) [conceptions].
They may also be intended to refer to [c] something entailing reward
or punishment, and praise (mad) or blame (dhamm). For us, this sense
is Legal (shar#), contra the Mu#tazila.40
These three definitions represent distinct ethical stances that alRz, as we will see, eventually develops into a coherent teleological
38
39
40
57
58
chapter two
Malib, 3, 10.
Nihya, fol. 195a.
Arba#n, 246; cf. Nafs, 1920; Ma#lim, 86.
This is discussed in more detail, p. 156 ff. infra.
Nihya, fol. 199b.
59
For such a person, killing and pillage are good, the more brutal
the better.
Now, we saw in the previous chapter how al-Rz concludes that
all human motives and value judgements are rooted in, and reducible
to, the two basic sensations of pleasure and pain. He contends that we
know immediately (bi-l-arra) that we seek some things and incline
towards them and are repulsed by others. From these inclinations,
our value judgements are formed. He posits the question of whether
these inclinations and judgements have, at their core, some primal
inclinations from which they ultimately emerge, or not. If not, then
either infinite regress or circular interdependence of inclinations on
50
51
Malib, 3, 347.
Malib, 3, 3501.
60
chapter two
According to al-Rz, that we do make value judgements independently is a self-evident and inarguable fact. However, as the true
nature of value can only be discovered through rational reflection, our
knowledge of it is not immediate, but discursive. For the Mu#tazila,
by contrast, both the truth of moral judgements and the essences
of moral values can constitute immediate knowledge. A Mu#tazil
may argue that all rational men accept that lying is bad, and that
when anyone is asked to explain this statement, he will affirm that
the badness of lying is intrinsic. Al-Rz rejects the latter claim and
argues that in generally-accepted convention (al-#urf al-#mm al-mashhr), what people mean by the expression evil (sharr) is pain and
what leads to it .53 Yet, in itself, this conventional usage does not
constitute evidence for the immediacy of this knowledge. Indeed,
he accepts that some people will make value judgements, believing
(wrongly) that value is intrinsic to acts.
A metaethical theory of moral judgement and motivation of the
sort that al-Rz advances is often described as an egoism, or, given
its emphasis on the primacy of the prudential and pleasure-seeking
motives, a hedonism. Yet, al-Rzs theory does not amount to a
crude hedonism; for he outlines a hierarchy of divisions of pleasure
and pain, which (as we will see below) differ according to which
part of the person experiences them. Joy is a non-physical type of
pleasure, and grief a non-physical type of pain, whereas the expression pleasure is often used narrowly for purely physical pleasure.54
He continues:
The benefit that is sought for its own sake is either pleasure or joy,
and the harm that is avoided in itself is either pain or grief. So it is
necessary to investigate which is stronger: pleasure or joy, pain or grief.
52
53
54
61
We say that this varies from soul to soul. There are those who prefer
bodily pleasure, while others prefer joy.55
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
Malib, 3, 24.
Malib, 3, 349.
Malib, 3, 34850.
Cf. p. 489 supra.
Malib, 3, 289.
See p. 89 infra.
Mulakhkha, fol. 326a.
62
chapter two
but, when used in certain context, they only aim to persuade (iqn#)
common people.
Moral statements, thus, either express emotions, or evoke them
in an audience, in which case they will be prescriptive. As such, the
seemingly factual, descriptive statement, Lying is bad, will be tantamount to the imperative, Do not lie! This stance, which al-Rz
adopts form Ibn Sn, is reminiscent of contemporary non-cognitivist
moral theories (both emotivist and prescriptivist), including the socalled Boo! Hoorah! approach to moral expressions. It is interesting
that al-Rz takes it to heart more than Ibn Sn does, whom he
criticises in his discussion of the theory of emanation for using such
a value statement as a premise:
He states in the Book of Demonstration of the Shif" that if you find the
knowledge-seeker62 saying, This is noble; that is base, then know that
he is confused.63 Somy goodness! (layta shi#r)how does he allow
himself here to use this rhetorical premise in the present scientific
discussion!64
63
64
chapter two
be Gods acts, and the acts of obligated agentsbe they obligatory acts
(wjibt), recommended acts (mandbt) or permissible acts (mubt)as
well as the acts of the unaware, the sleeper and animals. It is more
appropriate than saying, The good is what is Legally permitted,
since it follows from it that Gods acts are not good.67
67 Mal, 1/1, 136; cf. Nihya, fol. 199b200b, where the point is made in
reply to a Mu#tazil objection relating to the same problem (cf. #Abd al-Jabbr,
Mughn, 6/1, 107).
68 Arba#n, 246; cf. Mal, 1/1, 15960; Muaal, 479.
69 Nihya, fol. 200b.
65
70
66
chapter two
67
73
74
75
Ma#lim, 867.
Malib, 3, 28990.
Malib, 3, 290.
68
chapter two
69
70
chapter two
(b) Benefits that are needed (ja), but do not reach the level of
necessity (e.g. allowing property rental).85
(c) Complementary benefits (tasn), which are neither necessary
nor needed (e.g. public morality).
2. Religious and other-worldly (ukhraw) benefits, served by spiritual
and moral discipline.86
The Lawgiver endorses (i#tabara) some forms of convenient action
and proscribes (algh, abala) others.87 In qiys, if a scriptural ruling
on a given act appears to serve a certain benefit, commensurate
rulings may be established on other acts that serve similar benefits.
What, then, of convenient acts that the Lawgiver neither endorses
nor proscribes? We are referred to a subsequent discussion in the
Mal, on unsupported interest.
So we turn to a chapter, presented after discussing the four primary Legal sources, on other types of Legal evidence that jurists
have disputed. The first type regards the original state (al) of acts.
Al-Rz writes:
Early in this book, we showed that no rulings (l ukm) [apply to acts]
before the Law [is established], and we responded to the objections
of opponents.88 Now we want to show, using Legal evidence, that the
original state for benefits (manfa#a) is permission (idhn), and for harms
it is proscription (man#).89
85
71
93
72
chapter two
al-anbiy") and the objective of revealed laws (al-maqd min al-shar"i#).
The Qur"n and the sunna indicate that, sometimes explicitly, at other
times on account of rules that are prescribed in accordance with what
we outlined.99
99
100
101
102
73
Moral Obligation
The distinction between the moral is and ought was recognised by
classical mutakallimn. The Mu#tazila contended, not only that acts can
be intrinsically good (asan) or bad (qab), but also that unaided reason
knows (sometimes immediately) that human agents are obligated to
perform some good acts, which thus constitute duties (wjib), and to
omit some bad acts.104 On the other hand, though Ash#ars reject
objectivist conceptions of moral value entirely, they often declare
that their most serious point of contention with Mu#tazil ethics
concerns how moral obligations could be established by unaided
reason. By contrast, they maintain that both value judgements and
obligations are established by divine command.
Acts that, according to the Mu#tazila, constitute rational obligations include some that seem to affect none but the agent. One is
obligated, for instance, to omit vain acts and self-injury. However,
most rational obligations that the Mu#tazila affirm concern acts
that essentially do not serve the interests of the agent himself, but
relate purely to other creatures (especially human beings), or to God.
These include the obligation to enjoin good and forbid evil (al-amr
bi-l-ma#rf wa-l-nahy #an l-munkar), to thank the benefactor (shukr almun#im), and to omit lying, wrongdoing and wrongful killing.
The deontological view that certain acts constitute duties on
account of their intrinsic moral value is rejected completely in a
self-regarding consequentialism of the type that al-Rz upholds. In
line with classical Ash#arism, he maintains that theological reflection
(naar) and thanking the benefactor are not obligatory on the agent
prior to the reception of revelation.105 Notwithstanding, we find that
103 Unsupported interest was of course discussed by other pre-Rzian jurists.
Al-Ghazl is particularly relevant since he appears to be the first Ash#ar jurist to
present a consequentialist metaethics. One would expect him to develop a consequentialist normative ethics. Yet he does not.
104 #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 14, 150.
105 The obligatoriness of rational speculation is based on Revelation (sam#),
contra Mu#tazils and some Shfi# and \anaf jurists (Muaal, 134; cf. Mal,
74
chapter two
al-Rz indeed uses the term wjib in a non-scriptural sense, viz. that
it is incumbent on the agent to avoid harms that may affect him.106
Al-Ghazl too uses wjib in this sense; George Hourani translates
it as prudentially necessary, and explains that it is predicable of
an act, when from the standpoint of self-interest its performance is
preferable to its omission in a decisive way, i.e. when severe and
certain harm to the agent is to be expected from omission of the
act.107 He then notes:
Any theory in which obligation is related entirely to the interest of the
agent is regarded as analysing obligation in a prudential, rather than
ethical, way; or rather as totally substituting the concept of obligation
with a totally different one.108
75
110
76
chapter two
114
115
116
117
118
119
77
cism, but the alternative explanation that al-Rz provides for the
phenomenon of beneficent action. This will provide insight into his
approach to non-Legal obligation.
He first affirms his commitment to his own theory of value:
We have shown that benefit is sought in itself, and that harm is avoided
in itself. All that leads to preponderant benefit is good, and there is no
other meaning to its goodness. All that leads to preponderant harm is
bad, and there is no other meaning to its badness.120
The Mu#tazila, however, point out that we know by our minds that
acts can be both bad and beneficial, or both good and harmful. AlRz lists four such cases that they cite. (a) Though the wrongdoer
benefits from his wrongdoing, he will still know that wrongdoing is
bad. Elsewhere, he cites the following Mu#tazil argument:
Though wrongdoing is harmful to the one wronged, it benefits the
wrongdoer. The establishment of justice will benefit one individual,
but harm another. Paying a deposit back will benefit the recipient, but
harm the giver. If these cases are judged by the inclination or aversion
in the disposition, the wrongdoer will judge wrongdoing good, while
the one wronged will judge wrongdoing bad.121
However, the Mu#tazila maintain that this is not the case. They also
cite (b) the case of a highly eloquent poem, which is composed well,
written in fine calligraphy and recited beautifully, but which contains
blasphemy. The mind (#aql) will recognise that such a poem is bad,
despite the pleasure that will be found at the level of the natural
disposition (ab#) in reading, and listening to, it.122 Also, (c) though the
liar benefits from his lying, he will know, by unaided reason, that it
is bad.123 (d) One who finds a sick blind man on the verge of death
in a desolate desert will know by reason alone that he is obligated
to help, even where he expects that his help will only burden him
and not benefit him in any way (e.g. he may expect never to meet
him again for his favour to be returned, nor to be praised by other
people, as no other person is present, nor to receive afterlife reward,
as he may be an atheist).124
120
Malib, 3, 66.
Nihya, fol. 199a.
122 Cf. Mal, 1/1, 169.
123 Al-Rz cites a similar argument from #Abd al-Jabbrs Qur"nic commentary
(Tafsr, 16, 222).
124 Malib, 3, 67.
121
78
chapter two
125
126
127
Malib, 3, 68.
Malib, 3, 69; Nihya, fol. 198b199b.
Lawmi#, 15960.
79
Al-Rz accepts that even wrongdoers will generally consider wrongdoing as such to be bad. But how would the agents interests be
undermined by his denial of such norms?
Al-Rzs response to the second Mu#tazil example then introduces
the most crucial notion in this discussion. Judging the beautiful,
blasphemous poem to be good, he argues, will be contrary to the
advantages of the world, or public wellbeing, (mali, or malaat
al-#lam) in various ways.129 First, if such blasphemy were tolerated,
Gods commands and prohibitions would lose their influence on
peoples hearts, leading to bloodshed and anarchy (al-harj wa-l-marj).130
Second, God is the highest of all beings and the most beneficent to
the needy. If blasphemy against Him were allowed, it would not be
possible, as al-Rz puts it, to use the aid of virtues (fa"il) in averting
harmswhich contradicts public wellbeing. Third, he argues in the
Mal that tolerating such poems would lead to the degradation of
the virtuous, which would be contrary to human wellbeing.131 All
three (non-Legal) grounds for judging the poem bad are non-deontological: the badness of blasphemy is in no way intrinsic.
This is in clear contrast to the classical Ash#ar approach, whereby
the blasphemous poem would be bad purely by Gods prohibiting
blasphemy. It is also noteworthy that al-Rz does not approach
128
Malib, 3, 68.
He also speaks of the order of the world (nim al-#lam) (Mal, 1/1,
180; Nihya, fol. 200a; Tafsr, passim.). Though the falsifa used this expression in
a cosmological sense, it was widely used in reference to social order, which is the
sense that al-Rz intends (e.g. al-Mward, Adab, 2, 242 ff.; Miskawayh, Tahdhb,
127; al-Tawd, Hawmil, 233; 310).
130 Elsewhere (Malib, 3, 291), he refers to this discussion: [We stated that]
wrongdoing, though beneficial to the wrongdoer, is extremely harmful to the condition of the world (wa# al-#lam). For if we were to judge wrongdoing good, bloodshed
and anarchy would prevail, and no one would trust ones spouse and partner. This
is one of the greatest harms.
131 Malib, 3, 68; Mal, 1/1, 170.
129
80
chapter two
this problem from his own Legal standpoint, despite its applicability; viz. that the agent finds the poem and its recitation deplorable
solely because tolerating and enjoying it would be contrary to his
own afterlife benefits.
His response to the third Mu#tazil example follows a similar line:
the liar benefits from his lying, but knows that lying is bad, since to
allow it would contradict human wellbeing. Lying would undermine
the bases for much of human action and pursuit, rendering them
futile. The person lied upon will waste his time, or in some cases
much of his life, suffering much anguish consequently. For this reason,
lying contradicts human wellbeing, whereas truth-telling preserves
and advances it.132
On the fourth Mu#tazil example (the blind man in the desert),
al-Rz writes:
Among the conditions that contribute to preserving human wellbeing
is inculcating the desire (targhb) of beneficence among people, with the
hope that were the like of that state to occur to [the agent] himself,
they would act compassionately toward him. Since this aspect was
found to serve public wellbeing, people evidently consented (ialaa) on
[considering] it good and [considering] omitting it bad. Since people
have become accustomed to this convention (iil), agreed upon it,
and adhered to it throughout their lives, these states have unmistakably
become well-established in their hearts and minds.133
We need now to look into the nature of this link that al-Rz makes
between moral norms and public wellbeing (a theme that does not
appear in classical kalm). First of all, it is clear that the preservation of social order and wellbeing requires a general acceptance
of these norms. However, it is not immediately clear, within a selfcentred consequentialism, how any individual would be motivated
to contribute to the preservation of social order by accepting such
altruistic norms. For these will be of no immediate benefit to him,
but may delimit his freedom to further his own interests, or may
even disadvantage him.
Al-Rz appears to hold that virtually every individual (including wrongdoers) will be aware of the fact that it is not in their own
132 Malib, 3, 68; Mal, 1/1, 170; cf. Tafsr, 16, 222: Lying undermines the
wellbeing of both the world and the self.
133 Malib, 3, 69. Contrast this to the Ash#ar explanation through generic
sympathy.
81
interest (nor in anyone elses) that anarchy prevails. From this, the
individual will realise that the preservation of social order will serve
his own interest (along with the interests of other members of society),
and will thus be necessary from a prudential standpoint. Al-Rz
writes in Nihya al-#uql:
If the wrongdoer declares (aft) that wrongdoing is good, someone
else will soon wrong him. Since, in his natural disposition, he hates
that anticipated wrongdoing, and since all that leads to what is hated
is itself hated in the natural disposition, wrongdoing will indeed be
hated by the wrongdoer. The same applies to all other [commonlyaccepted moral norms].134
134
135
82
chapter two
83
139
140
Malib, 3, 70.
See Shihadeh, From al-Ghazl to al-Rz, 1649.
84
chapter two
the good to be good in essence and the bad to be bad in essence is
a false claim.141
Mu#tazils then say: This argument does not apply to what we say.
For we do not say that the good is good in essence and that the bad
is bad in essence. Rather, we say that the good is good on account
of aspects (wajh) that relate to it, and the bad is bad on account of
aspects that relate to it.
At this point, Ash#ars say that explanation with reference to aspects
is neither comprehensible (mafhm) nor conceivable (ma#ql).
We will here explain these aspects, such that what is intended in
them may become comprehended. We say: ... Man may want to take
a particular medicine. What determines that want is not the essence of
that medicine, but a combination of things, including the occurrence
of certain humours in the body, the unavailability of other medicines
and the appearance of symptoms of illness in the body. The combination of these states (l) will produce the want to take that medicine. If
you know this, know that there is nothing below the lunar sphere that
will necessitate anything by its essence (li-dhtih wa-li-#aynih). Rather,
necessitation and determination will occur at the combination of states,
aspects and conditions.
Mu#tazils, therefore, say: We do not say that what makes killing bad
is solely its being killing. Rather, what makes it so is the combination
of a number of things, namely its being an occurring pain, not for a
previous offence, nor for a subsequent compensation (#iwa). And so
forth with all good and bad things.
It thus appears that those who have relied on this argument to refute
the claims of the Mu#tazila did not know their position and did not
address all their views.142
85
86
chapter two
This being the case, the goodness or badness of things is not due to
the essence of the act, or to an attribute concomitant to it. ... Therefore, it must be an attribute of the agent. Yet this attribute cannot
be [a] the agents being a knower, for knowledge follows from what
is known, but does not affect it; nor [b] his having power, for power
only effects existentiating the act, which does not vary among good
and bad [acts]; nor [c] his having will, for that would make wrongful
killing ... good if the agent intended it to be good.149
149
150
151
87
the notion of speech within the self (kalm al-nafs), a doctrine upheld
by Ash#ars, relevant mainly to the question of the uncreatedness of
the Qur"n.152
In the Malib, he cites another possible Mu#tazil counter-argument: that, within his own consequentialist framework, he himself
admits that speech may be judged as good or baddoes this not
contradict his argument? Al-Rz responds that he does not evaluate the act of speaking in itself. Rather, the meanings that lying
produces within the listener, which do not communicate to him a
correct understanding of the true state of affairs, may motivate him
to act in a way that is disadvantageous (e.g. if futile or harmful) to
him. For this reason, people will judge lying as such to be bad.153 As
such, consequentialist judgement does not face this same difficulty
as deontological judgement, since it does not concern the act itself,
but its subjective consequences.
Therefore, while the ethical objectivism of the Baghdd Mu#tazila
is refutable on account of the ethical ontological claims that they
make, the ethical objectivism of the Barans is refutable for their failure to justify their claims ontologically. As regards the metaphysical
status of morality, if the ethical ontology of the Baghdds is false,
the ethics of the Barans appears utterly nonsensical.
Ethical Epistemology
Nonetheless, al-Rz gives his opponents the benefit of the doubt. He
realises that Mu#tazil ethical theory is most seriously challenged at the
epistemological level, which becomes his primary focus. Thus the last
two sections of Book 3 of the Malib (introduced by al-Rzs above
criticism of classical Ash#ar objections to Mu#tazil ethics) provide
an account and a refutation of Mu#tazil ethical epistemology.154
He cites the common Mu#tazil view that the knowledge of some
ethical truths is immediate (arr), that of others acquired (kasb),
or inferential (istidll).155 For the latter type, the Mu#tazila rely on
arguments ad hominem (ilzm) and purported proofs (m jar majr al-
152 Al-Bqilln (Inf, 158) writes: Real speech is the meaning (ma#n) that exists
in the self, and has signs (amra) that indicate it, e.g. verbal and written speech.
153 Malib, 3, 3356; cf. 3, 349.
154 Malib, 3, 34158.
155 Malib, 3, 341; Nihya, fol. 198a; cf. #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 63.
88
chapter two
156
157
158
8.
159
160
5).
161
Ul al-dn, fol. 263; fol. 267; Ishra, fol. 34b35a; Mal, 1/1, 1801; Nihya,
fol. 201b. Cf. M. Marmura, A Medieval Argument for the Intrinsic Value of the
Moral Act, esp. 1237, an examination of this Mu#tazil argument and some classical Ash#ar refutations thereof.
89
162 Ishra, fol. 35a; Nihya, fol. 198b; cf. al-Ghazl, Mi#yr, 14950; Mustaf,
1, 49; Ibn Sn, Ishrt, 1, 1878. On al-Ghazls borrowing from Ibn Sn in
this regard, see M. Marmura, Al-Ghazl on Ethical Premises, 395; Hourani,
Ghazl, 81.
90
chapter two
dispositions, rather than to make them actually free from them. The experience
(tajriba) occurring at the assumption of being free [from dispositions] is
other than the experience occurring at being truly free [from them]. We
experience the former case, though what is conducive to our purpose
is the latter. Therefore, this [Mu#tazil] argument is false.163
163
91
166
92
chapter two
Al-Rz asks: What does saying, one may (la-hu)171 or may not
perform a particular act, mean? It could have a number of senses,
including: (1) permission for, or prohibition against, performing it;
(2) capability or inability to perform it; (3) a certain attribute of the
agent, as we say of a body that it has (la-hu) the attributes blackness and motion; (4) the acts being good or bad, which entails
that the agent may or may not perform it accordingly; and (5) some
sort of permission or prohibition that issues from unaided reason.
Yet the first sense will result in a divine command notion of moral
value, which Ab l-\usayn does not intend. The second and third
are obviously not intended. The fourth is a tautology. In the fifth,
if rational prohibition is other than the agents desert of blame or
punishment (as in the second definition), then what is it exactly?
What else, al-Rz adds, could la-hu here possibly mean? This crucial element in Ab l-\usayns definition appears meaningless and
renders the whole definition meaningless.
The thrust of al-Rzs argument is that rights and duties depend
on the moral status of acts. One would normally answer the questions, What may I do?, What ought I to do?, What ought I
not to do?, etc., by reference to what is good or bad, but not vice
versa. To say that the bad is what one may not do presupposes that
one knows what one may not do and why one may not do it. Yet
knowing why one may not do it is to know why it is bad; al-Rz
170
Nihya, fol. 193b194a; cf. Mal, 1/1, 1326; al-Bar, Mu#tamad, 1, 363
69.
171
La-hu is difficult to translate into English while preserving its various senses
and connotations. I find may preferable to has the right to, or is entitled to.
93
172 #Abd al-Jabbr defines bad as what the agent deserves blame for (Mughn,
6/1, 7; 6/1, 267) and rejects defining it as what the agent may not perform since:
(a) there are bad acts that one cannot avoid performing, e.g. the acts of the child
and the sleeper (these further highlight the ambiguity of the phrase, laysa lahu an
yaf #alah); (b) knowledge that the agent may not perform an act is more properly an
entailment (ka-l-tbi#) of its badness (cf. al-Rzs objection); and (c) this definition
does not unveil what [the act] is bad on account of, and does not draw attention
to the judgement (ukm) connected to it, viz. the desert of blame.
173 Nihya, fol. 194ab.
174 Cf. Muaal, 81; Mulakhkha, fol. 1b2a.
94
chapter two
175
95
Only after knowing all these complex details, after a process of subtle
and specialised speculation, will one grasp the complex conception
of wrongdoing. However, al-Rz objects:
The mutakallimn are unanimous on that whenever knowledge of the
principle (al) is discursive (naar), it will be inconceivable for derivative knowledge (far#) to be immediate. Knowledge of the essence of
wrongdoing is undoubtedly a principle for knowledge that it is bad.
Knowledge of the essence of wrongdoing can only be attained through
this definition that only critical investigators can conceptualise by the
means of intricate speculation. Since knowledge of this principle is
discursive, it will be inconceivable for knowledge that wrongdoing is
bad to be self-evident.181
In other words, it follows from the Mu#tazil claim (that such ethical statements are self-evidently and immediately true) that one
who states, Wrongdoing is bad, without having a conception of
wrongdoing, will effectively be saying: Wrongdoing, which I do
not know what it is, is self-evidently bad. If the conception itself
is unknown, then no attributes of it can be self-evident. For selfevident assertion requires only the presence of the two conceptions
of subject and predicate in the mind, and will follow from their
presence immediately, without syllogistic intermediation. If at least
one of these conceptions is not present in the mind, the truth of
any statement of assertion that involves both cannot possibly be
known self-evidently.
The Mu#tazil may then modify his position by contending that
the badness of wrongdoing will be known immediately by one who
already conceives the essence of wrongdoing, not by everyone. This,
according to al-Rz, will be to admit that the badness of wrongdoing is not self-evident universally for all rational humans, as the
Mu#tazila originally claim. And indeed he rejects even this modified
position.182
Lastly, al-Rz also cites the Mu#tazil argument that when we
180 Malib, 3, 353; cf. #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 13, 298. On Mu#tazil views on
how the infliction of pain becomes bad, cf. M. Heemskirk, Suffering in the Mu#tazilite
Theology, 122 ff.
181 Malib, 3, 354; cf. Nihya, fol. 198b.
182 Malib, 3, 3545.
96
chapter two
183
184
185
Malib, 3, 355.
Mal, 1/1, 171.
Malib, 3, 289.
97
98
chapter two
190
Muaal, 483.
Muaal, 483; cf. Arba#n, 249.
192 Nihya, fol. 200b.
193 Mal, 2/2, 17990; cf. the good commentary by al-Ifahn, Kshif, 6,
289301.
191
99
194
Al-Rz gives the example of fornication, which is the ratio for the desert of
punishment. The link between act and punishment is based on divine command:
Whenever you see a man fornicating, then know that I have made it obligatory
(awjabtu) that he be punished. So fornication merely indicates the applicability of
punishment, but does not cause it (Mal, 1/1, 13940).
195 Mal, 2/2, 191 ff.
100
chapter two
196
197
198
101
199
102
chapter two
203
Malib, 3, 2956.
Malib, 3, 298304; cf. Mal, 1/2, 36398; 2/2, 2578; 2/2, 2602; Nihya,
fol. 202b.
205 On the badness of futile action according to Mu#tazil ethics, see Oliver
Leaman, #Abd al-Jabbar and the Concept of Uselessness.
204
103
104
chapter two
Therefore, if Gods speech were untruthful, it would entail an imperfection (naq) in His essence, which is inconceivable.
Al-Rz also quotes Ab Isq al-Isfar"ns argument that the
speech within the self (kalm nafs) relates to a thing in accordance with
the knowledge of [that thing]; therefore, it cannot contain lying.212
208 Mal, 1/2, 37880; Arba#n, 237; Munart, 512; Tafsr, 2, 42 ff.; Ma#lim,
856; Malib, 3, 30515. Cf. al-Ash#ar, Ibna, 195; al-Juwayn, Irshd, 2034. One
commentator (al-Ifahn, Kshif, 4, 3) writes: Al-Juwayn writes, in the Shmil,
that what most of the answers of our shaykh ... al-Ash#ar ... are inclined to, and
what those knowledgeable among his companions have adopted, is that obligating
the impossible (mul) is rationally conceivable, and so is obligating something and
determining the constant obstruction from it.
209 Cf. #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn, 6/1, 67.
210 Lying is inconceivable in relation to God, not because of [its] badness
(qub), but because of its impossibility in relation to Him by rational evidence
(al-Bqilln, Tamhd, 343; 105).
211 Ul al-Dn, fol. 268.
212 Ul al-Dn, fol. 109; cf. al-Juwayn, Irshd, 27882; al-Kiy al-Harrs, Ul
al-Dn, fol. 140b.
105
213
214
106
chapter two
215
Mu#tazil objection: Nihya, fol. 86a; al-Rzs reply: Nihya, fol. 92ab. Cf.
al-Juwayn, Irshd, 25782.
216 Al-Rz explains: If I close my eyes for a moment, then open them, I will
know for certain that God is capable of turning the walls into gold during that
moment, and then, when opening my eyes, returning them as they were. This
possibility will not undermine the immediate knowledge that that did not take
place. The same is true of all customary events. ... Therefore, the possibility of
things and events departing from their normal courses (majr-h al-#diyya) does not
undermine the immediate knowledge that they will continue upon their courses
(Nihya, fol. 92b).
217 Al-Juwayn, Irshd, 275; cf. Arba#n, 317; Malib, 8, 614 (where al-Rz does
not consider it to be a strong argument).
218 Malib, 8, 979. Cf. Arba#n, 324; Nihya, fol. 92b.
107
219
220
221
108
chapter three
109
CHAPTER THREE
Al-Rz is indeed the first theologian to juxtapose these three definitions of value terms in such a succinct manner. This appears in a
work as early as the Ishra, where he writes that good and bad,
... also designate attributes of perfection (kaml) and imperfection (nuqn).
So it is said, Knowledge is good; ignorance is bad. By perfection,
we mean that a thing has something it is supposed to have (wujd shay"
li-shay" min sha"nih an yakna lahu), with respect to its species, type, or
essence.2
The same listing of the three definitions is also found in his later
works.3 Though it is unprecedented in kalm to list these contrasting
definitions of value terms in this way, this third definition seems
related partly to a sense that classical Ash#ars recognised in a main
class of value terms as used in ordinary language and some technical contexts. Nonetheless, as we have seen, they explained this sense
as being descriptive of non-moral facts about beings, and often
appealed to it in explaining divine attributes, such as justice and
wisdom.4 Thus, Ibn Taymiyya appears to be right in his remark
that this third definition represents a falsaf influence.
1
2
3
4
110
chapter three
Ul al-Dn, fol. 351 ff.; Ishra, fol. 63a; Nihya, fol. 248a; 263b265b.
Cf. Shihadeh, From al-Ghazl to al-Rz, 1723.
Ul al-Dn, fol. 243; cf. Tafsr, 4, 2314; 8, 189.
Risla f l-nafs, fol. 2a; cf. Nafs, 48.
111
... is neither the physical body nor physical, but is a spiritual substance
that emanates on this frame, animates it, and uses it as an instrument
to acquire sciences and knowledge. Once it perfects its substance by
them and knows its Lord and the rights of His creatures, it will become
prepared to return to His presence and to become one of His angels
eternally happy.9
This highlights the link between the nature of the soul and the
purpose of its coming into being.
Al-Rz frequently argues that, as with pleasure and pain, likewise
perfection and imperfection are simple primary human ends that
are sought or avoided in themselves. The two types of motivation
are not mutually exclusive: That pleasure is liked in itself does not
conflict with perfection being liked in itself.10 Indeed, in Kitb al-Nafs
wa-l-r, he argues that both are mutually explanatory:
We know spontaneously (bi-l-badha) that we like (aabba) one thing and
dislike (kariha) another. Therefore, we say: Either there is one thing
that is liked in itself, and another that is disliked in itself, or ... each
thing is liked because it involves something else, or disliked because
it involves something else. The latter division is absurd, since it will
lead to either infinite regress or circularity. ...
Having reflected and meditated (baathn wa-ta"ammaln), we have
found nothing that can be said to be liked in itself except pleasure
and perfection. In reality, there is no difference between them; for
what is pleasurable will bring about the perfection of state for the
experient of pleasure (kaml l al-multadhdh), and what constitutes an
[aspect of] perfection will be pleasurable. However, we refer to what
is physically pleasurable pleasure, and to what is spiritually pleasurable perfection.
Also, what is disliked in itself is pain and imperfection. In reality,
there is no difference between them, as explained already; for perfection is liked for its own sake, in itself, qua perfection (mabb li-dhtih
bi-dhtih min aythu anna-hu kaml), and imperfection is disliked for its
own sake, and in itself, qua imperfection.11
112
chapter three
13
14
15
16
17
18
113
19
20
21
114
chapter three
their own sake. Therefore, one may love God in Himself and for
His own sake (f dhtih wa-li-dhtih), whereas loving His service and
reward constitutes an inferior level of love.
Pleasure being loved in itself does not conflict with perfection being
loved in itself. This being the case, we say: Those who interpret love
(maabba) of God, exalted, as love of obedience (#a) to Him, or love
of His reward, know that pleasure is loved for its own sake, but not
that perfection is loved for its own sake. As for knowers, who maintain
that God is loved in Himself and for His own sake, they have realised
that perfection is loved for its own sake.22
God is the most perfect being, in His necessary existence and self-sufficiency, and in His attributes of knowledge and power. The greater
the knowledge of God that one attains, the more will his yearning
(shawq) and love of Him be.
Similarly, the classical mutakallimn interpret Gods love for human
beings in terms of His will (irda) that reward (thawb) be delivered
to them. In the Tafsr, al-Rz writes that they are able to support
this interpretation only be arguing that since there is no evidence
to affirm love as a distinct divine attribute, it ought to be denied.
He replies, In Nihyat al-#uql, we have shown that this method is
weak and vacuous (a#fa sqia).23 By this method, he refers to the
argument ad ignorantiamthat if something has no proof, it should
be negatedwhich indeed he rejects in the Nihya.24 By contrast, he
asserts that it is likely that the love of God, exalted, for the servant is
an attribute other than His will that reward be delivered to him.
The second theme is the question whether angels or prophets,
who are the best of mankind, are superior (afal). Most previous
Sunnis (with the notable exception of al-Bqilln and Ab #Abdullh
al-\alm) and Sh#s maintain that prophets are superior, while the
falsifa and Mu#tazils hold that angels are superior.25 In most of his
writings, al-Rz maintains that prophets are superior, though, in the
Arba#n, he seems undecided and more inclined to the opposite view.26
22
Tafsr, 4, 232.
Tafsr, 14, 132.
24 Nihya, fol. 6a; cf. A. Shihadeh, From al-Ghazl to al-Rz, 165.
25 Arba#n, 368. In Tafsr, 2, 2156, he writes that the majority of Sh#s contend
that angels are superior.
26 Arba#n, 36884; cf. Ul al-dn, fol. 325; Muaal, 531 ff.; Khamsn, 667;
#Ima, 33; also Tafsr, 2, 215 ff., which is directly inspired by al-Shahrastn, Milal,
2, 944; see p. 1378 infra.
23
115
While much of the evidence given for both views is Qur"nic, the
most important rational argument for the superiority of prophets is
as follows. Humans have more encumbrances than angels: they are
afflicted with appetite, irascibility, forgetfulness and other internal
motives for disobedience, as well as the corruptive influence of the
devil and external causes of doubt. Therefore, it will be harder
(ashaqq) for humans to be obedient [to God]; and what is more difficult
is superior.27 Angels do not suffer from the same shortcomings as
humans, which affect both their will and knowledge, so they perform
good acts effortlessly out of their perfectly good and pure nature, and
on the whole have a rather easy life. Yet, typically in action-oriented
ethics, effort and hardship are the main criteria for moral superiority.
The generosity of a poor man donating a small sack of wheat may
be much more praiseworthy than that of a wealthy man donating a
thousand pieces of gold. Al-Rz explains superiority ( fal) here in
terms of the size of the reward (thawb) earned.28
In his latest works, he turns away from this action-oriented stance
to a character-oriented perfectionism, and contends that angels are
superior to prophets. He writes: Know that the mind of one who
knows what an angel is, and what its attributes are, will not allow
him to delve into this question. Yet most people think that angels
are birds that fly in the heavens! So they delve into this question.29
The essence and attributes, rather than the acts, of an agent become
the primary criteria for superiority, which no longer refers to the
consequences of acts, but the excellence of the agent, his intrinsic
worth of character.30 Responding to an argument for the superiority
of prophets to angels, al-Rz writes that angels possess perfection in
both power and knowledge: Yet excellence ( fala) has no meaning
except this. Thus, since they are superior to men [in these respects],
they will be more excellent than men.31 In the Arba#n, he records
the following argument for the superiority of angels:
Angels are free from appetite, irascibility, imagination and estimation
attributes which act as thick veils from the manifestation of the lights
of God, exalted. There is no perfection except by that manifestation,
27
28
29
30
31
Arba#n, 36970.
Arba#n, 370; 371; Tafsr, 2, 216; 2, 232.
Malib, 7, 405 ff.; cf. Ma#lim, 1012.
E.g. Malib, 7, 414; 7, 418.
Malib, 7, 4101; cf. 7, 421 ff.
116
chapter three
and no imperfection except by the intervention of that veil. Since
[angels] always contemplate this manifestation, while human souls
are usually veiled from [it], we conclude that there is no comparison
between their perfections and human perfections.
To say that service (khidma) when many obstacles are present is more
indicative of sincerity than service without obstacles is fanciful (kalm
khayl). For the bulk of acts of worship and obedience are intended for
the realisation of that manifestation. The greater and the further from
obstacles the realisation of that manifestation is, the more complete
will the perfection and happiness be.32
The contemplative ideal replaces the earlier voluntarist trend in alRzs earlier thought, which gives primacy to the notions of volition,
choice, effort, practice, responsibility and desert. Thus, adherence to
theological creeds and performing acts of worship become means,
rather than ends in themselves.
Human Perfection
The question of the reality of man (aqqat al-insn) is one that alRz found to be highly problematic. He acknowledges in his late
work the Malib that it is a dilemma, about which the strangest fact
is that something so close to us could be so obscure.33
In his earliest works, he accepts the common classical kalm view
that the essence of man is purely physical. In the human body, he
writes in the Ishra, there are core parts (ajz" aliyya) that will neither
cease to exist nor be replaced; this is the reality of man.34 Slightly
later, in Nihyat al-#uql, the reality of man is said to be nothing but
the physical body (hdhih al-bunya, hdh al-badan).35
Later, under philosophical and Sufi influence, he rejects this physicalism and advances a thorough critique thereof, in favour of a
dualism of a physical body and a separate, rational and unphysical
soul. He often refers to previous Sunni scholars, and sometimes to
others as well, apparently to illustrate that this later doctrine is neither unorthodox nor irrational.36 The present section will examine
32
33
34
35
36
117
118
chapter three
42
119
another type may be vile, evil and stupid, these same characteristics
will appear in their respective human souls, both in their essences
and in the effects they receive from them in their lives. This is why
two strangers may meet and immediately feel either affinity or enmity
toward each other, depending on the types of their souls. Al-Rz
adds that while this model is merely a plausible hypothesis, it is
verified empirically by talisman specialists.48
On the basis of his theory of the variation of human souls, al-Rz
sometimes expresses a psychological determinism with respect to
human character, to the extent that change in character traits appears
impossible (this is to be distinguished from his standard metaphysical
determinism with respect to human action). The differences among
human souls are akin to those that exist among different animal
species: donkeys, horses, wolves, lambs, etc.49 Many people with
malevolent traits have inherently malevolent psychological essences;
though they may modify their behaviour, their essential natures will
remain unchangeable:
We see a man, who may be naturally evil and abject. If he were to
undergo the maximum possible discipline, he would not depart from
his malevolent nature. Rather, he may become, through discipline
and admonition, such that he will avoid those acts and not perform
them. Nevertheless, if he then abandons his self to its original nature,
it will incline to that evil. Also, his temperament may change from
warmth to coldness, from wetness to dryness, and vice versa, yet what
is concomitant to his inborn nature will not change.50
In one place, al-Rz argues that since the essential traits of human
souls can be neither eliminated nor modified, one who is happy
(sa#d) will not become miserable (shaq); and vice versa.51 However, he seems to maintain such radical ethical determinism only
in relation to the extremities in the scale of human psychological
excellence: some individuals are doomed by the sheer baseness of
their souls, whereas others are blessed by the excellence of theirs.
Despite his insistence that altering the essence of the human soul is
48
Tafsr, 16, 183; 19, 20; 19, 112; Malib, 7, 1423; 7, 2667; 7, 272; 7, 400; 8,
136; 8, 144; Ma#lim, 115; Shar #Uyn al-ikma, 2, 284; Jabr, 356; Al-Sirr al-maktm,
1104. Cf. Ab l-Barakt, Mu#tabar, 2, 38894.
49 Malib, 7, 1478.
50 Nafs, 86; cf. Jabr, 36; Kamliyya (Ar.), 901; (Per.), 118.
51 Tafsr, 14, 144; cf. Malib, 1, 557.
120
chapter three
52
121
56
57
58
122
chapter three
59
123
68 Nafs, 22; 131; Malib, 1, 260; Tafsr, 12, 173; 17, 216. Cf. al-Ghazl, Iy",
4, 3007.
69 Nafs, 223; 12830.
70 Nafs, 245.
71 E.g. Nafs, 144.
72 Nafs, 256.
124
chapter three
73
74
75
76
125
77
126
chapter three
127
not eat or copulate, their state is superior to that of beasts. Al-Rz retorts that this
is a highly rhetorical argument and rests on the assumption that angels experience
pleasure (Mulakhkha, fol. 325b6a; Shar al-Ishrt, 2, 87; cf. Ibn Sn, Ishrt, 4, 10.
Al-Rz accepts Ibn Sns arguments earlier in Mabith, 2, 4267).
88 Mulakhkha, fol. 326ab (also quoted by al-Bursaw, Tahfut, 1245); cf. Ma#lim,
1134.
89 Cf. Ibn Sn, Shif", Ilhiyyt, 2, 429.
90 Cf. Ibn Sn, Mubatht, 1978; 210.
128
chapter three
human soul acquires true conceptions of all separate primary principles,
asserts them apodictically and demonstratively, knows the final causes
for universal motions to the exclusion of particular ones, fathoms the
form of the entirety [of being], the relations among its various parts,
and the order that initiates from the First Principle to the lowermost
existents in its hierarchy, understands providence and its manner, and
recognises how the entity that is superior to all is distinct in its existence
and oneness, how it knows, without any multiplicity or change whatsoever being attributed to it, and how existents are related to it.91
Attaining these cognitions will require the mastery of both metaphysics and physics, which implies that only a philosopher can attain
theoretical perfection. By contrast, al-Rz maintains that happiness
may be attained only by knowing God, whereas other intellectual
pursuits may distract from this end. One ought to,
... view His creatures qua their requiring a producer who possesses
the attributes of perfection, since knowing them in any other respect
will oppose [the attainment of] this happiness. I have learnt this from
experience (tajriba).92
Human souls may acquire a sense of yearning (shawq) towards knowing God by becoming aware of His being and by contemplating
signs of design in His creatures. When the love (#ishq; maabba) of
God becomes established in the heart, the heart will be repulsed
by all else. Yearning, al-Rz explains, transpires when man gains
some awareness of God, but perceives Him neither constantly nor
completely; he will then desire to attain purer and more complete
and constant knowledge of Him. In this world, mans knowledge
of God will inevitably be obscured to some extent by the distorting
veil of the imagination, which will be lifted in the afterlife. Yet man
will not attain complete knowledge of God in either world, since
the degrees of knowing God are endless. The journey is thus endless, and the degrees of human perfection are infiniteno human
being has ever reached complete knowledge of God. If one attains
complete knowledge of an object of knowledge, his yearning for it
91 Mabith, 2, 429; cf. Ibn Sn, Shif", Ilhiyyt, 2, 429; 2, 4256; Najt, 331.
On Ibn Sns views on this question, see Yahya Michot, La destine de lhomme,
467, n. 78.
92 Mulakhkha, fol. 327a; cf. Tafsr, 4, 233. Cf. al-Ghazl, Iy", 4, 30810.
129
130
chapter three
97
Malib, 8, 7100.
Cf. Ibn Sn, Awl, 11426; Ithbt al-nubuwwt, 417.
99 Ibn Sn, Ithbt al-nubuwwt, 47.
100 On Ibn Sns theory of prophecy, see: Y. Michot, La destine de lhomme, 118
ff.; H. Davidson, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect, 116 ff.
98
131
that organise human life and association, and are thus necessary for
human wellbeing (al). Therefore, he concludes, divine providence
(#inya) will necessarily provide prophets for mankind.101
Despite his early Ash#arism, al-Rz seems to accept this theory
of prophecy in the Mabith, one of his earliest falsaf works, where
he often follows Ibn Sn closely. His discussion of prophecy here is
generally paraphrased from Ibn Sns works, including the notions
of the appearance of the prophet being a socio-political necessity,
the special psychological nature of the prophet, and the process of
revelation.102
However, in the later Mulakhkha and Shar al-Ishrt, al-Rz totally
rejects Ibn Sns theory of prophecy. Against his psychological explanation of supernatural events (including miracles, the visual perception of angels and the reception of revelations), al-Rz argues, for
instance, that such events could have other natural explanations.103
Also, against Ibn Sns teleological explanation to prophecy, he
presents the following argument in Shar al-Ishrt:
What is the meaning of your saying, Since people in this world need
a lawgiver, his existence will be necessary (wjib)? ... If you mean that
it is obligatory on God to create and existentiate him (as the Mu#tazila
say, Compensation is obligatory upon God, i.e. that if He does not
deliver it, He will deserve blame), then that will go against what the
falsifa claim in the first place.
However, if you mean that since the existence of the prophet brings
about the order of this world, and since it has been proved that God
is the source of every perfection and good, it will be necessary that
God causes that person to come into being, then this too is false. For
we say: Not all that is most advantageous (ala) to this world will
happen necessarily in this world. For had the people of this world
been naturally disposed to goodness and virtues, that would have been
more advantageous than their present condition; yet that is not the
case. Therefore, it is conceivable for the existence of the prophet to
101
132
chapter three
be more advantageous than his non-existence, yet for [no prophet]
to ever exist!
If he meant something else, then that ought to be explained, so that
we may investigate its plausibility or falsehood.104
133
107 On them, cf. article Barhima, EI2; Norman Calder, The Barhima:
Literary Construct and Historical Reality.
108 Muaal, 5034; cf. Arba#n, 3279.
109 Muaal, 5124.
110 Muaal, 5149.
134
chapter three
prophecy, their combination is known, with certainty, to be found only
in prophets. This was the preferred way of al-Ji and was adopted
by al-Ghazl in his book the Munqidh.111
Al-Rz, in the Muaal, does not endorse this proof from the characteristics of the claimant of prophethood, and the listed benefits of
prophecy are not given in support of it. Instead, he writes:
What should be relied upon (al-mu#tamad) in [proving] the messengership of Muammad, peace be upon him, is his presentation of [the
miracle of] the Qur"n. All other approaches may be cited as complimentary evidence.112
Al-Rz here prefers the proof from miracles, but shows some interest in teleological approaches to prophecy.113
The Teleological Approach to Prophecy
In works later than the Muaal, probably from the Tafsr onwards,
al-Rz adopts a proof of prophecy akin to that attributed to al-Ji
and al-Ghazl, which he will now consider to be superior to the
proof from miracles. In the Ma#lim, he introduces it as follows:
In the first method [to proving prophecy], we prove [the claimants]
prophethood through miracles. Once his prophethood is affirmed, we
infer the truth of his sayings and deeds from this affirmation. As for
this [second] method, we show that all that he presents in speech and
action are the deeds of prophets; therefore, he will necessarily be a
truthful and true prophet, who is sent by God.114
111
135
Malib, 8, 104.
Ma#lim, 101.
118 Tanbh, 38. Ibn Sn (Shif", Ilhiyyt, 1, 186 ff.; cf. 2, 355) defines tmm wafawq al-tamm as the thing being perfect in a certain respect and providing benefit
of the same respect to other beings.
119 This, al-Rz writes, is the meaning of the adth, The scholars of my community are the likes of the prophets of the Israelites (Tafsr, 17, 115; cf. 19, 98).
However, he makes it clear that a non-prophet never reaches the level of any
prophet, and he criticises those who place #Al above some previous prophets (Tafsr,
8, 86; cf. Lawmi#, 3201).
117
136
chapter three
120
Tafsr, 17, 115; Ma#lim, 945; Malib, 8, 123. On these two types of demonstration, see al-Frb, Burhn, 26; Ibn Sn, Najt, 1034.
121 Al-Ji, \ujaj, 12834.
122 Al-Ji, \ujaj, 1367. A Qur"nic reference is implied (Qur. 4:165).
123 Al-Ji, \ujaj, 1567.
124 Al-Ghazl writes: If you understand what it is to be a prophet, and have
devoted much time to the study of the Qur"n and the traditions, you will arrive
at an immediate knowledge of the fact that [Muammad], peace be upon him,
is in the highest grades of prophethood. Convince yourself of that by trying out
137
what he said about the influence of devotional practices on the purification of the
heart. ... When you have made trial of these in a thousand or several thousand
instances, you will arrive at an immediate knowledge beyond all doubt (Munqidh,
149; cf. 14450; W. Montgomery Watts translation, with modification, Faith and
Practice, 67).
125 Al-Ghazl, Munqidh, 14950.
126 Tafsr, 19, 98. I have not found this distinction in any of al-Ghazls works.
The closest seems to be al-Risla al-Laduniyya (cf. 69 ff.), which al-Rz refers to
expressly in a different context (Tafsr, 21, 149).
127 E.g. al-^j, Mawqif, 8, 261 (referring to the Malib); Ibn Taymiyya, Majm#,
4, 99; Khwansr, Rawt, 701 (quoting an earlier author, in reference to the
Ma#lim).
128 See p. 114 supra. Al-Shahrastn (Milal, 2, 944; cf. Mura#a, 1302) designates
this notion of prophecy as that of the \unaf", prophetic monotheists, who call to
the return to human primordial nature (fira), and are represented in his time by
(at least some) Muslims. (Elsewhere, he refers to Islamic sects that have departed
from al-Milla al-\anfiyya, 1, 36). They defend prophetology as an alternative to the
Sabian deification of spiritual entities (rniyyt). These are the two main creeds
that existed at the time of Abraham (1, 230). The discussion is represented as a
summary of debates that occurred between the two groups, yet it is clear that the
author is on the side of the \unaf" (cf. e.g. Hermes Trismegistos is not Sabian,
God forbid!, 2, 44; Abraham refutes Sabianism, 2, 53; cf. Nihyat al-aqdm, 4269;
4645), and that, regardless of whether he considers the debates real or not, the
138
chapter three
arguments directed at the Sabians are his own; yet he does not admit this, since
the Milal is meant to contain unbiased accounts of creeds (1, 16).
129 Al-Shahrastn, Milal, 2, 11 ff. Cf. Nihyat al-aqdm, 4634, where he refers
only to the prophets perfection, not his ability to perfect others.
130 Cf. al-Shahrastns brief account of Ism#l prophetology (Milal, 1, 193 ff.). On
his Ism#lism, see W. Madelungs introduction to his Mura#at al-falsifa (27).
In one place, al-Rz explains prophecy in terms akin to al-Shahrastns. He
writes that two worlds exist: the lower world and the world of spiritual beings
(rniyyt). There necessarily exists in the latter a being, the angelic messenger
(al-rasl al-malak), who is the highest of all beings in it, and the obeyed (mu#)
among them. Similarly, there will have to exist, in this lower world, one who is
the highest and the one obeyed in it, viz. the human messenger. The former will
be the source (madar), the latter the manifestation (mahar) (Tafsr, 1, 264; cf. Asrr
al-tanzl, 310. Cf. al-Shahrastn, Milal, 2, 15).
131 Malib, 8, 105; cf. 1, 261.
132 Malib, 7, 280.
139
133
On this notion, cf. |ub, EI2. The Sh#a, he adds, call him the infallible
(ma#m) imm and the lord of the age (ib al-zamn), and say he is hidden (gh"ib).
Al-Rzs interpretation is nevertheless heretical from the Imm point of view,
since he refers, not to the twelfth imm, Muammad al-Mahd, but to members
of a line of Sufi poles. He writes:
[The Imms] are correct in [their] descriptions [of this perfect person]. For
since he has none of the imperfections that are in others, he is exempt (ma#m)
from imperfections. He is the lord of the age because that individual is what
is intended in itself in that age. ... He is hidden (gh"ib) from people; for
people do not know that that individual is the best and most perfect of the
people of that cycle. I would also add that that individual probably does not
know that he is the best of the people of that cycle; for though he knows his
own state, he will not be able to know the state of others. Therefore, others
do not know who that individual is, and he does not know who he really is
(Malib, 8, 106; cf. 1, 260).
Al-Rz here argues that a main factor affecting this human hierarchy is climate,
the most perfect people being the inhabitants of Irnshahr, who will produce the
most perfect person of his time. Could this be a claim to be himself the renewer
(mujaddid) of faith at the end of the 6th century A.H.? Cf. Tony Street, Life and
Works, 415.
134 Al-Shahrastn, Milal, 2, 11 ff.
140
chapter three
that since there is a hierarchy of possible human forms of perception (idrk), there will have to appear actual representatives of each.
The prophet will be the human being in whom the highest type of
perception is actualised most perfectly.135
Yet, al-Rz introduces a subtle, but crucial, modification to Ibn
Sns proof of prophecy. For Ibn Sn, the necessity of prophecy is
ontological, and rests on his view that for a property to be potential
in some beings, it must be actual in at least one other being. In the
case of prophecy, the human psychological property in question is
intuition (ads).136 This is not an argument that al-Rz makes.137 In
contrast to Ibn Sns argument from metaphysical necessity, al-Rz
points out expressly that he bases his view that the appearance of
prophets is necessary on induction (istiqr"), which is of a type that
provides complete certainty (al-qa# wa-l-yaqn).138 He argues that
from observing natural beings, we recognise a hierarchy of beings
that constitutes a cosmological order. When we consider the hierarchy of elemental objects, we find that its main divisions (viz. the
mineral, the vegetative and the animal) are connected (muttail), such
that the highest species in the lower division is very similar to the
lowest species in the higher division. The same is true of their subdivisions and further subdivisions. Therefore, having found, through
observation, actual representatives for each level of possible beings,
except one level, we conclude that that level too must have some
actual representation. In the case of the human species, which is
the most superior subdivision of the animal type, since we find men
who are very close to beasts in their characteristics, we will expect
that some men who are very close to angels (the next higher form
of beings) in their characteristics should exist. In them, both the
theoretical and practical faculties will be so perfect and intense that
they will have access to higher knowledge and be able to perfect
others. They will possess angelic properties and be detached from
135
Ibn Sn, Ithbt al-nubuwwt, 427; cf. M. Marmura, Avicennas Psychological Proof of Prophecy.
136 Cf. M. Marmura, Avicennas Psychological Proof of Prophecy, 53;
D. Gutas, Intuition and thinking, 29 ff.; F. Griffel, Al-[azls Concept of
Prophecy, 1123.
137 Griffel (Al-[azls Concept of Prophecy, 1123) seems to suggest that
al-Rz uses the same line of argument as Ibn Sn.
138 Malib, 8, 105; 8, 107.
141
matter and have control over it, which will enable them to perform
miracles. Al-Rz writes:
[Such a person,] who is the most perfect of those perfect, and the best
of those most virtuous and knowledgeable, will be at the frontier of the
supernal horizon (ufuq) of humanity. You have come to know that the
end of each species is connected to the beginning of the more superior
species. Since the angels are superior to the human species, the end of
humanity will be connected to the beginning of angelhood. Since we
have shown that that man exists in the highest stages of humanity, it
becomes necessary that he be connected to the realm of angels and
that he be in their midst.139
139
140
Malib, 8, 107.
Al-Rghib al-Ifahn, I #tiqdt, 1201.
142
chapter three
141
143
145
144
chapter three
Rhetorical discourse presupposes the listeners constant and reverential acceptance of the orators words. However, if one uses the
same sorts of premises to discusses opinions (al-ql wa-l-ql), he will
become a dialectician and will compromise the halo of reverence
associated with rhetoric.149
Al-Rz thus argues that the art of rhetoric is superior to dialectic,
since dialectic persuades neither specialists nor common people,
whereas rhetoric persuades common people. Dialectic fails to persuade common people for three reasons. (a) Dialectical deductions
are subtle and beyond the minds of common people. (b) When a
common person becomes cornered by a dialectical deduction and
unable to reply, he will explain that by his ignorance of the reply,
not by the strength of the argument. (c) The dialectician assumes
a competitive and aggressive stance; therefore, if one believes that
another tries to subdue him and expose his weakness, he will be
moved to refute him and not to be persuaded by him. Al-Rz
continues:
Indeed, the arts that provide assent (iqrr) are demonstration and rhetoric. Demonstration provides certainty for specialists. Rhetoric provides
persuasion for common people. God, therefore, says: Call unto the
path of your Lord with wisdom (ikma) (i.e. demonstration) and kindly
exhortation (maw#ia asana) (i.e. rhetoric) and argue (jdil) with them in
the best manner.150 He mentions dialectic after these two arts, since
147
148
149
150
145
151
Shar #Uyn al-ikma, 1, 2523. Cf. Ibn Rushd, Fal al-maql, 45 ff.
Notwithstanding, al-Rz maintains that exalting God above all aspects of
similarity to created beings is, theologically, the correct position. Hence, Book 2
of the Malib is devoted to tanzh (cf. Malib, 8, 115).
153 Qur. 42:11.
154 Qur. 6:61.
155 Qur. 35:10.
156 Qur. 20:5.
157 Reading al-jabr, instead of al-khayr.
152
146
chapter three
method that was introduced by the master of all prophets, Muammad, peace be upon him. For he proclaims Gods greatness (ta#m)
in all respects to the maximum extent, in a general, concise way (#al
sabl al-ijml), and prohibits [men] from wading into details. So he
presents, in affirming deanthropomorphism, His saying, God is the
Self-sufficient and you are the needy.158 And if He is absolutely selfsufficient, it will be inconceivable that He be composite of parts; it
follows that He is not spatial; therefore, it will be inconceivable that
He exists in place and space. He also states, Naught is as His likeness. If He were a body, His essence would have been similar to all
bodies, since we maintain that all bodies are alike [in physicality]. He
then provides many statements in affirmation (ithbt), and he does that
to the maximum extent. This is necessary; for were He not to present
such statements, He would not have established [Gods] existence for
most people.
Also, he goes to the maximum extent in establishing His knowing
all objects of knowledge. So he says, With Him are the keys of the
unseen; none but He knows them;159 and He says, God knows that
which every female bears and that of which the wombs fall short of
completion.160 He then does not explain whether He knows by His
essence or by [an attribute of] knowledge.161
In many verses, He also explains that man is an agent, a knower, a
producer, a creator and an effecter. He then shows in all other verses
that all good and evil is from God, exalted. Yet He does not explain
how these two contentions may be reconciled; rather, He made general (#al sabl al-ijml) belief in both obligatory. He also explains that
nothing whatsoever escapes the decree of God, exalted, and His will,
judgement and determination. He then explains that [God] neither
wills nor performs wrongdoing, vainness or futility.
Therefore, the method (arqa) of our Prophet in his invitation (da#wa)
is to proclaim Gods greatness in all conceived respects, and to prohibit
wading into explaining whether these respects conflict or not. For if we
say, Bad acts are of the agency of men, and are created by God, we
proclaim His greatness with respect to power, but we do not proclaim
His greatness with respect to wisdom. And if we say, They are not
from God, we proclaim His greatness with respect to wisdom, but
we do not proclaim His greatness with respect to power.
As for the Qur"n, it proclaims Gods greatness with respect to both
power and wisdom together. Concerning the former He says, Say,
158
Qur. 47:38.
Qur. 6:59.
160 Qur. 13:8.
161 Which is a major problem in classical kalm. Cf. H. Wolfson, The Philosophy
of the Kalam, 112 ff.
159
147
162
163
164
165
166
Qur. 4:78.
Qur. 4:79.
Malib, 8, 1168.
Malib, 8, 1245.
Malib, 8, 119.
148
chapter three
167
168
169
Ma#lim, 112.
Malib, 8, 1212; cf. Ma#lim, 1034.
Shar #Uyn al-ikma, 2, 134.
149
150
chapter three
The commonly-accepted explanation of the obligatoriness of rational
reflection is [as follows]. Knowing God, exalted, is obligatory, and can
only be attained through reflection. What is a basis for a categorical
obligation, and falls within the capacity of the obligated agent (mukallaf), is obligatory, as will be explained in the [science of] the principles
of jurisprudence.172
Having the correct creed is Legally obligatory, in the same way that
performing certain acts is obligatory. According to classical Ash#ars,
this obligation stems purely from divine command, whereas the
early al-Rz departs with this view in favour of a consequentialist
notion of Legal obligation. The latter line of argument is used in
the Muaal:
Problem: The obligatoriness of rational reflection is based on scripture, contra the
Mu#tazila and some Shfi# and \anaf fuqah". Our evidence is: [1] [Gods]
saying, We would not punish until we had sent a messenger.173 [2]
Since the basis of obligation is [afterlife] reward and punishment, and
since none of Gods acts can be [morally] bad, the mind alone will
be unable to make conclusive judgements with respect to [afterlife]
reward and punishment. Thus, it will not be possible to arrive [by
autonomous reason] at the obligatoriness [of reflection].174
In classical kalm and classical theology generally, theological knowledge is necessary in as much as it is incumbent upon men to know
certain things about God and His relation to His creation. He is
worshiped fully only when this knowledge (or belief) is combined to
correct action. This stance was the main motive for the compilation
of creeds (#aqda). As such, the main function of Revelation, as far as
believers are concerned, is to communicate knowledge of the correct
creed and practice to which humans ought to adhere. Revelation acts
as a primary source for all types of theological knowledge, except
what is required for proving the veracity of Revelation itself. The
problem that all theologians had to deal with was to harmonise what
seem to be conflicting theological assertions in revealed texts. Most
mutakallimn choose to interpret some statements metaphorically
(ta"wl). However, in his later works, al-Rz maintains that theological
statements in revealed texts provide only a minimal theology, since
their primary purpose is soteriological, rather than epistemic.
172
173
174
Muaal, 130.
Qur. 17:15; cf. Qur. 10:101, which al-Rz cites elsewhere.
Muaal, 134. Cf. al-f, Dar", 98.
151
175 Malib, 7, 230; Tafsr, 12, 534; 20, 104; Lawmi#, 170. He often mentions
that ta#m and shafaqa are specified in a adth, which I have been unable to find.
Instead, #Abd al-Qdir al-Jayln (d. 561/1166) (Fat, 106) cites it as a non-Prophetic
aphorism: Good lies entirely in two words: al-ta#m li-amr Allh #azza wa-jalla,
wa-l-shafaqati #al khalqih. Al-Rz writes that all things should be viewed as Gods
creatures and as signs for His oneness and greatness, and should consequently be
given due respect. Living creatures, which experience benefit and harm, should
be treated with great compassion, e.g. through filial piety and enjoining good and
forbidding evil (Tafsr, 15, 24).
176 Malib, 8, 124. Cf. al-Mward, A#lm al-nubuwwa, 52. Al-Rz replies by
this to an argument against the possibility of prophecy, made from the same perfectionist notion of the human good that he uses to justify religion: assuming that
revealed religion aims to serve human perfection, one religions abrogation of a
previous one is unjustifiable. For the later religion will abrogate either the perfectionist aspects of the previous one, thereby contradicting its purpose, or inessential
details, in which case great harms will follow from frivolous differences (Malib,
8, 879). Al-Rz also accepts the traditional justification for abrogation from the
corruption of previous religions (Malib, 8, 1212; cf. Ma#lim, 1034).
177 Malib, 8, 12737. Thus, revelation is not a consequence of the psychological faculties of the prophet, but depends on his hearing Gods speech directly, or
receiving it via Gabriel, who acts as an intermediary (Malib, 7, 3899; 7, 421).
In contrast to Ibn Sns theory, whereby the imagery that appears in scriptural
texts stems partly from the prophets faculty of imagination in its interaction with
the Active Intellect and the heavenly souls, and partly from the prophets own
judgement and manipulation of the form and content of scripture, al-Rz considers both the form and content of scripture as completely divine. Gabriel receives
Qu"nic revelation in exactly the same form he communicates to the Prophet
(Tafsr, 27, 188). Cf. Tafsr, 2, 32: Gabriel heard Gods speech in the heavens, and
brought it down unto the Prophet. ... If it is said, How did Gabriel hear Gods
speech, when His speech, according to you, is of neither letters nor sounds? we
152
chapter three
153
Private sphere
Public sphere
179
180
Perfectionism (supra-mundane,
spiritual wellbeing)
Revelation (shar#a, Qur"n).
Practical ethics (akhlq).
Rational reflection (naar).
Spiritual discipline (riya).
All serve to perfect the
individual both theoretically and
practically.
154
chapter three
155
CHAPTER FOUR
156
chapter four
157
transient and (b) inextricably mixed with pains and detriments, and
(c) vile people have a greater share of them than virtuous people.
However, he notes, this reasoning presumes that though they ought
to be avoided for these accidental features, these pleasures are essentially good.2
By contrast, the falsifa argue that sensory pleasures are inherently
contrary to the human good and human happiness. In this regard,
two distinct propositions are advanced: (a) that these pleasures are
real, but essentially base; and (b) that they are not real, but are mere
relief from pain.
As mentioned, al-Rz considers the former proposition and arguments for it to be rhetorical.3 And, indeed, many of the arguments
he lists are akin to the three he attributes to poets and orators.4 For
example, he cites the inductive argument that observation shows
that all people hallow ascetics and despise indulgent pleasure-seekers,
which will indicate that human primordial nature (fira) attests to the
baseness of these pleasures.5 Other arguments emphasise that the
physical pains and ailments that result from eating and coition are
severe, numerous, long-lasting and often spread in more than one
organ in the human body. By contrast, the pleasure experienced in
eating decreases sharply after the first morsel or two, whereas coital
pleasure occurs only during orgasm, which is as though an instant
(al-n alladh l yanqasimu).6 And so forth; many of these arguments
are commonplace.7
In what follows, we shall focus on the latter, possibly demonstrative
proposition, that sensory pleasures, thought to be [real] pleasures,
are actually not pleasures, but little more than relief from pain.8
Al-Rz argues that the experience of sensory pleasure presupposes
the existence of prior needs (ja) and appetites (shahwa). Thus, if
one were to offer jewellery to a dog and a bone to a man, neither
would find pleasure in the object offered, since neither would have
Dhamm al-ladhdht, 6.
See p. 61 supra.
4 Cf. Nafs, 88107; Malib, 7, 297302.
5 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 11. This is an argument from widely-accepted beliefs, which
al-Rz will consider to be non-demonstrative, but rhetorical (cf. p. 88 ff. supra).
6 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 13.
7 Cf. p. 122 supra.
8 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 6.
3
158
chapter four
desire for it. Also, the greater the hunger, or the longer the period
of abstinence from coition, the greater the pleasure experienced at
gratificationwhich indicates that the extent of pleasure depends
on the extent of the preceding urge.9
Yet, other parts of the text seem non-committal with respect to
this view; e.g. the statement, These states are either not pleasures,
or, if they are pleasures, they are extremely base and most vile.10
It is not entirely clear in Dhamm al-ladhdht to what extent al-Rz is
committed to the view that pleasure is unreal. This ambiguity appears
to stem from the rhetorical style of this moral text, which was written
with a view to persuade the reader into shunning sensory pleasures,
rather than to analyse the nature of pleasure as such.
In any case, al-Rz concludes this section by stating the global,
quantitative assessment that pain is predominant in this world,
which is closely related to his qualitative view on the nature of
pleasure and pain. He writes: What prevail over the people of this
world are anguish, affliction and grief, whereas pleasure and good
are very rare.11
But does al-Rz truly adhere to such a pessimistic stance, or is it
merely a ploy that largely serves the rhetorical purpose of a moral
text? It will be instructive to explore his treatment of these themes,
viz. the nature and extent of pleasure and pain, in his philosophical
works, which lie at the background of Dhamm al-ladhdht.
The Nature of Pleasure and Pain
In the Mabith and the Mulakhkhatwo relatively early falsaf
worksal-Rz opens the section on pleasure and pain by quoting Ab Bakr al-Rzs definitions of pleasure as departure (khurj)
from an unnatural state (i.e. towards the natural state), and pain
as departure from a natural state.12 The only two possibilities,
therefore, are the natural state, which is neutral, and unnatural
states, which are comparatively bad. But there cannot be a state
superior to the natural state. From this, Ab Bakr al-Rz arrives at
the view that pleasure is nothing but relief from pain; and there is
9
10
11
12
159
not a pleasure that occurs but after a pain,13 a view that he also
attributes to Plato.14 Al-Rz reports:
Some deny the existence of pleasure, viz. Muammad Ibn Zakariyy
al-Rz. He claims that the reality of pleasure is nothing but the negation of pain. Thus, the reality of the pleasure found in eating is nothing
but the negation of the pain of hunger; and the reality of the pleasure
found in drinking is nothing but the negation of the pain of thirst. ...
Most falsifa and mutakallimn reject this claim.15
In the Mabith and the Mulakhkha, he rejects this view and cites
examples of pleasures that cannot be explained in terms of a return
to a natural state from a previous unnatural state, thus appearing to
be real. One such instance is the enjoyment of a pleasant sight that
one does not conceive of beforehand, which, he argues, contradicts
the claim that pleasure from sight is due to the negation of the pain
of longing.16 The change in the state, al-Rz argues, is in fact only
accidental to pleasure, rather than essential.
He then turns to Ibn Sns definitions of pleasure as perceiving what is agreeable (idrk al-mul"im), which is the realisation of
perfection in an aspect of the perceiver, and pain as perceiving
what is disagreeable (munf).17 However, is pleasure this type of
perception, or a product thereof (which, he notes, is suggested by
Ibn Sn in at least one place)?18 Al-Rz argues for the latter view:
We perceive, in the acts of eating, drinking and coition, a specific
state that is distinct from all other psychological states, the same
being true of the perception of pain.19 Therefore, as sensory perceptions (issiyyt),
... the essences of pleasure and pain are perceived as a priori, self-evident
conceptions (taawwur awwal badh). Indeed, conceiving them is among
the clearest, most evident and most incontrovertible cognitions. But
13
160
chapter four
the purpose of definition and description is to define what is obscure
with what is clear.20
Just as statements of assertion (tadq) relating to ones sensory experiences do not require demonstration, the conceptions (taawwur) they
involve do not require definition. Hence, the essences of pleasure
and pain are known without definition.21
Every rational being, indeed every sense-perceptive being (asss), perceives [pleasure and pain] in oneself and, necessarily, differentiates
between both and between these and other things. What is so is indefinable. This shows that the view of those who maintain pleasure to be
the perception of what is agreeable, and pain the perception of what is
disagreeable, is false. For the conceptions pleasure and pain are more
evident than the conceptions agreeability and disagreeability.22
Al-Rz also cites medical evidence, which shows that though some
physical ailments are sensed by the individual, they do not produce
pain. This indicates that pain is not simply the perception of an
unnatural state, and that the latter is not even a sufficient condition for pain.
Objections to Neoplatonist Theodicy
Discussions of the nature of pleasure and pain are often pertinent
to more macro-level questions regarding cosmogony, the problem
of evil and the assessment of human existence as a whole. Perhaps
the most striking example of such a link can be seen in Ab Bakr
al-Rzs conclusion that evil is prevalent in this world, which follows from his notion that pleasure is purely relief from pain. This
conclusion is not expressed clearly in any of his surviving works,
but is reported in the following hostile account by Maimonides (d.
601/1204):
[He] has written a famous book, which he has entitled [the Ilhiyyt].
He filled it with the enormity of his ravings and his ignorant notions.
Among them there is a notion that he has thought up, namely, that
there is more evil than good in what exists; if you compare mans
wellbeing and his pleasures in the time span of his wellbeing with the
pains, the heavy sufferings, the infirmities, the paralytic afflictions, the
20
21
22
161
wretchedness, the sorrows, and the calamities that befall him, you find
that his existencehe means the existence of manis a punishment
and a great evil inflicted upon him. He began to support this opinion
by inductively examining these misfortunes.23
162
chapter four
25
26
27
163
good for the sake of a little evil, and the predicate is a great evil.
If, by a great evil, which is the predicate, [they] mean omitting a
great good, the predicate of the proposition will be identical to its
subjectwhich makes the statement meaningless. Or, if [they] mean,
by great evil, great pain, then this statement will mean Omitting a
great good for the sake of a little evil is a great pain. However, this
is obviously absurd; for had these things not existed, pain, pleasure,
evil and happiness would not have occurred.28
By affirming what good and evil mean in ordinary language, alRz counters Ibn Sns ontological and cosmological theodicy with
the very human experience of suffering. This is what minds and
hearts become perplexed by, and consequently what any attempted
theodicy ought to address. Ibn Sns theodicy merely circumvents
the real problem of evil.
28
29
30
164
chapter four
31
165
ing that evil is indeed prevalent in this world. The view is presented
most definitively in Shar al-Ishrt, which al-Rz considers to contain
his most comprehensive refutation of Neoplatonic theodicy.35 In
comparison to his earlier works, the Mabith and the Mulakhkha,
he here seems more favourable to Ab Bakr al-Rzs denial of the
reality of pleasure, though he does not accept it. He writes that
even if it is conceded that pleasure can be real, observation shows
that most pleasures are unreal and that real pleasures are extremely
rare, whereas all pains are real. As does Ab Bakr al-Rz before
him, al-Rz argues from particular empirical examples from daily
human experience.36 Health is merely the absence of physical ailments and pain, and is, therefore, not pleasurable. Eating, drinking,
coition, wearing garments, dwelling in houses, and experiencing
a cooling breeze on a warm day, are not pleasurable, but merely
alleviate the pains of hunger, thirst, coital desire, cold and heat,
respectively. He adds:
What is prevalent over the conditions of men is either pain or the
relief from pain, whereas the occurring pleasure, which is an existent
phenomenon (kayfiyya wujdiyya) other than the negation of pain, is
extremely rare, as if a drop in an ocean, such as finding pleasure in a
sight, sound, etc. that is unknown before being perceived. As for pains,
they are untold, though some are extremely severe, such as illnesses,
while others are mild, which are things that one is preoccupied with
most of his time, such as afflictions, anxieties, fear, dread, shyness, anger,
pains that occur at hunger, thirst, working in trades and professions,
smelling pungent smells, meeting imbeciles, seeing odious sights, the
harms caused by flies, flees, lice and ants, as well as all other things
that are too numerous to recount.
If it is proven that pains are preponderant (ghlib) and that real
pleasures are unprevailing (maghlb), and if those few pleasures were
the purpose of creation and existentiation, then, given the Creators
knowledge of the occurrence of numerous pains, ... the prevalent evil
would be for the sake of an unprevailing good. It becomes evident
that what [the falsifa] claim, viz. that good is preponderant in this
world, is false. Let it not be said that though disease is widespread,
health is prevalent. For we will say that we have shown that health
is a non-existent state (la #adamiyya), which is mans being free from
35
Therefore, he omits the discussion in the Muaal (478) and simply refers
the reader to Shar al-Ishrt.
36 Cf. Maimonides citation, p. 1601 supra. On this kind of argument against
optimism, cf. Eric Ormsby, Theodicy, 9 ff.
166
chapter four
both pleasure and pain. ... Therefore, remaining in non-existence is
preferable (al-baq" #al l-#adam awl).37
37 Shar al-Ishrt, 2 801; cf. Arba#n, 2945. This view is echoed in various
places in al-Rzs writings; e.g. Tafsr, 19, 71 (meter: awl):
167
Indeed, both the virtuous and the morally neutral, combined, are
as a drop in the ocean.39
In his wider assessment of the human condition and his criticism
of Neoplatonic theodicy, al-Rz only asserts that most pleasures are
unreal, specifically in relation to worldly pleasures. Yet he avoids Ab
Bakr al-Rzs claim that pleasure as such is unreal, which will exclude
even the possibility of spiritual pleasure.40 For this reason, he does
not arrive at global pessimism. At the end of the section on theodicy
in Shar al-Ishrt, he concludes on a highly personal note:
As for me, though God has bestowed wellbeing (salma) upon me in most
conditions, so that I am as though distinct in this from most [people],
if I go back to myself and compare real (aqq) pleasures (i.e. excluding
unreal (#adam) ones) to pains, both external and internal, as we have
listed, we will find pleasures so wretched in comparison to pains. This
being the case, how could such pleasures, in relation to these pains,
be desirable! Were it not for the great afterlife pleasures that we long
for, it would have been best to have remained non-existent.41
39
40
41
168
chapter four
Some then contrived (itla) to find cases where pleasure was affirmed
without involving relief from pain. However, assuming such cases are
valid (though their validity is in fact questionable), they are rare.
As such, it does not become true that good prevails. Rather, pain
and the negation thereof prevail, whereas pleasure is rare. Thus, their
argument42 will backfire, since evil is prevalent (ghlib); or, if not prevalent, it is on a par [with good]. This being the case, to initiate creation
would be either foolish (safah) or futile (#abath).
[As for Ibn Sn]s claim that separating good from evil is not possible, we say that this presupposes the denial of divine choice. Otherwise, [God] is capable of creating an object such that it is hot when it
is needed for a benefit, and not hot when it becomes harmful.43 Know
that deliverance from these confusions is possible only by upholding
one of two claims: [a] that God is a necessitating cause, in which case
this whole dispute will be nullified; or [b] that God is a voluntary agent,
alongside the denial of ethical realism (al-usn wa-l-qub), and that He
cannot be questioned for His acts,44 which is the clear truth.45
42 I.e. the Neoplatonic argument that since the world is predominantly good,
not to create it would have been bad. God thus creates the world necessarily, since
He is absolutely good.
43 He explains this more clearly in the Mabith (2, 523): Burning that occurs
after fire is not necessitated by fire. Rather, God chooses to create it immediately
after (#aqba) contact with fire. If the occurrence of burning after contact with fire
is by the choice and will of God, exalted, then He can choose to create burning
when it is good, and not to create it when it is bad.
44 Qur. 21:23.
45 Mulakhkha, fol. 350b51a.
169
There is neither a need nor a basis for theodicy, even if one were
to accept such an extreme pessimism as advanced by Ab Bakr alRz. Gods acts need not, and cannot, be justified morally.
Socio-Political Pessimism
It transpires from the foregoing that the view presented in the first
section of Dhamm al-ladhdht concerning the nature of pleasure and
the prevalence of suffering in this world represents a genuine stance
to which al-Rz is committed, especially in his later philosophical
writings. Yet, as a moral text, Dhamm al-ladhdht employs a rhetorical
form of discourse and pays less attention to rigour, exactitude and
the overall perspective. The same is true of the second section of this
work, which deals with what al-Rz terms imaginative pleasures,
i.e. pleasures experienced within the faculty of imagination in connection to the individuals involvement in the external world.
Much of the interest of this second section of Dhamm al-ladhdht
46
For Ab Bakr al-Rz, Soul is one of the five eternals, the others being
God, matter, space and time. Cf. his Al-Qawl f l-qudam" al-khamsa in his Ras"il,
191216.
47 See Malib, 4, 40119. Cf. Marwan Rashed, Ab Bakr Al-Rz et le Kalm,
416.
48 Malib, 4, 419.
170
chapter four
lies in its being one of the few places in which we find glimpses of
al-Rzs socio-political thought. Again, what we find in this section
is not a complete, or even rudimentary, socio-political theory, but
a moral treatment of aspects of the human socio-political condition,
focusing especially on the subjective experience, which is nonetheless
a crucial part of al-Rzs socio-political thought.
The Original State of Human Social Nature
Introducing this second section of Dhamm al-ladhdht, al-Rz states
that his purpose is to show (a) that the pleasures of rule and high
status (ri"sa wa-jh) can only be accompanied with great hardship
and severe pains, and (b) that these pleasures are in themselves
vile and unworthy.49 For these contentions, twenty arguments are
advanced.
The first argument is most instructive. Al-Rz writes:
Every man desires that he becomes the ruler over others, and that all
else falls under his domination, control and power. For mans being
dominant over the other and in effective control over him is an attribute of perfection; and attributes of perfection are desired for their
own sake. Ones being dominated by another and under his control is
an attribute of imperfection; and attributes of imperfection are hated
in themselves. Therefore, the natural disposition (ab#) of each person
drives him to be the ruler over the other and in control over him,
and to disallow the other from becoming a ruler over, and controller
of, him.
Therefore, the seeker of the attainment of rule for a particular man
is that particular man alone, whereas all others seek to undermine that
rule and to obliterate it. That single man is thus the only seeker of
the attainment of that rule for himself. As for all other people, from
east to west, they all seek to undermine it, negate it, and obliterate it.
Hence, on the one hand, those who seek to realise this aim cannot be
fewer in number, for there cannot be fewer than one, while, on the
other hand, those who seek to undermine and negate it are very great
in number, for it is evident that everyone other than that one will seek
to negate that rule and to undermine that persons supremacy.50
49
50
51
171
52
53
54
55
56
172
chapter four
whoever aspires to attain leadership will invite people to kill him and
will increase their interest in destroying and eliminating him.57
With respect to any given attribute, every individual will be superior, equal, or inferior to others. Superiority to others in a given
attribute will motivate them to undermine it as much as possible,
either by attempting to eliminate it if it is a destructible attribute,
such as power, or by attempting to obscure it if it is an indestructible
attribute, such as knowledge. Equivalence to others in a particular
attribute will lead to a similar outcome, since uniqueness (wadniyya;
tafarrud) is an attribute of perfection, while sharing an attribute with
others is an attribute of imperfection. Finally, though by inferiority,
one escapes the active and determined enmity of others, one will
become treated despicably, as any other vile and lowly thing. This
type of relation is not only symptomatic of human interaction, but
is a universal principle:
Physicians even say that whenever a particular organ becomes weak,
stronger organs will send all [their] refuse to it. On the whole, the
domination of the strong over the weak is of the concomitants of being
(min lawzim al-wujd). So it becomes evident that the state of man always
falls in one of these three categories. ... Therefore, this corporeal life
is never dissociated from sorrow, grief and heartbreak.58
Dhamm
Dhamm
Dhamm
Dhamm
al-ladhdht,
al-ladhdht,
al-ladhdht,
al-ladhdht,
20.
21.
189.
23.
173
all, both ruler and ruled, oppressor and oppressed, great pains and
detriments. Human social existence, as one facet of mans wretched
worldly existence, is inescapably a life of ceaseless strife, tension
and merciless struggle to prevail, evade detriment and survive. The
greater the struggle, the greater the risks of detriment and death,
and the more violent the likely outcome.
The following passage, which appears in the Tafsr as a commentary
on the greeting Peace be upon you (al-salmu #alaykum), presents a
vivid depiction of the original state of human nature.
There is no doubt that this world is a hotbed for evils, detriments,
calamities and terrors. Scholars who investigate the obscure aspects of
human character (akhlq) differ on whether the origin of the nature of
the animal (al-al f jibillat al-ayawn) is good or evil. Some say that its
origin is evil, and that all human individuals are as though in perfect
agreement on this.
We may complement this by adding: Indeed, even all animals are
as though in perfect agreement on this! The evidence to this is that
whenever a man sees another man whom he does not know running
towards him, he will be driven by his nature to take guard against him
and to prepare to repulse him. Had his natural disposition (ab#) not
testified that the original nature of man is evil, primordial mind (firat
al-#aql) would not have necessitated the preparation to repulse the evil
of that comer. They even say that this feature appears in all animals;
for every animal, which finds another animal running towards it, will
escape and take guard against it. So, had it been evident in its natural
disposition that the original nature of this comer is good, it would
have necessitated it to stay where it was; for the original disposition
of [animal] nature motivates it towards desiring the attainment of the
good. ... So we know that the original state in the animal is evil.
Therefore, we say: Averting evil is more important (ahamm) than
attaining good. This is indicated by a number of aspects. First, averting evil involves preserving the original state, which is more important
than attaining more. Second, delivering the good to everybody is not
within capacity, whereas abstaining from harming anybody is within
capacity, since the former is action, whereas the latter is abstention. ...
Third, if evil is not averted, evil will occur; and this will result in the
occurrence of pain and grief ...; but if goodness is not attained, man
will remain in neither good nor bad, but in original wellbeing. ...
So it becomes evident [1] that the averting of evil is more important
than the attainment of good; [2] that this world is the hotbed of evils,
detriments, calamities and afflictions; and [3] that the animal, in the
origin of its created nature and the necessity of primordial disposition,
is a source for evil. Therefore, when a man reaches another man, the
most important consideration will be to inform him that, in relation to
himself, he is in a state of peace, security and safety. So, it has become
174
chapter four
conventional (iil) that [the comer] should initiate the greeting, which
is for him to say, Peace be upon you!61
From the foregoing, al-Rz seems to conclude that good and just
government is virtually impossible, and that political activity involves
great unavoidable detriment to both subjects and political agents.
The ruler will often find himself in great dilemmas, forced to choose
between two or more equally evil options.62 For instance, he may
act either humbly and benevolently, or despotically and brutally,
towards his close associates: either way, he will live in constant fear.
Humility and benevolence are bound to weaken his power, whereas
brutality will motivate others to kill him, or to eliminate his rule.
If it is said that balance (tawassu) is required, then, al-Rz argues,
the nature of this balance is unknown.
Also, just rule should involve appointing qualified individuals in
positions of power. Yet, al-Rz argues, such rule is an ideal that
either never occurred, or is extremely rare. Unjust rule, on the other
hand, will bring upon the ruler the enmity and condemnation of all
sensible and pious men.63 A just and widely satisfactory distribution
of wealth also appears to be an unsolvable dilemma.64
Some of the arguments put forth in Dhamm al-ladhdht seem to
conclude that the individual has many good reasons to minimise his
social association (mukhlaa) and political involvement, or even to
abandon it altogether (farra; i#tazala). However, man is political by
nature (madan bi-l-ab#). For if one were to live in reclusion (tafarrada)
in a desert, away from the material, moral and intellectual benefits
of urban life, he would lose his human attributes and descend into
bestiality. Thus, whether or not one becomes socially involved, one
is bound to suffer great harms.65 Indeed, even the most rudimentary
forms of social association will involve unsolvable dilemmas: Man
may live in this world with or without spouse and offspring: each
option will be a cause for suffering detriments and calamities!66
Family life will cause suffering to the individual in various ways,
including the constant obligation upon him to manage the familys
61
62
63
64
65
66
245.
29.
2930.
256.
27.
175
67
68
69
70
71
Dhamm al-ladhdht,
Nafs, 1416; cf. p.
Dhamm al-ladhdht,
Dhamm al-ladhdht,
Dhamm al-ladhdht,
28.
124 supra.
19.
22.
25.
176
chapter four
Social Contract
Had the purpose of the second section of Dhamm al-ladhdht been to
present a comprehensive account of socio-political motivation, we
would have judged the conclusion (that the agents socio-political
involvement is based completely on a calculation that takes into
account only his immediate interests) as fairly crude. What it presents,
rather, is a view of human social nature at its most basic and indications as to how this view may be developed into the foundation for a
full-fledged socio-political theory. Thus, the argument that individuals
may cooperate for a non-personal cause each out of sheer self-interest may become a ground for a more sophisticated utilitarianism. It
will do justice to al-Rz to append the above examination of his
notion of human nature with an outline of what elements could be
found in his kalm works of a fuller socio-political theory.72
Calculations of self-interest may yield more complex conclusions,
whereby the interests of the social agent are often not gained in any
immediate way. We saw above that al-Rz presents a theory of
consent in order to explain both moral norms and the sense of moral
obligation in human beings.73 The sheer brutality and insecurity
of the original, unchecked state of human association, as described
in Dhamm al-ladhdht, will drive individuals to the conclusion that
adhering to a set of norms will define the framework to realising a
state of security to each individual. Their primary motive will be
prudential, since each individuals life, freedom, wellbeing, property
and interests will be at risk from being undermined by others, which
is a risk that even the opportunity to gain at the expense of others
will not make worthwhile. According to al-Rz, reason is generally
more inclined to prudence than to the pursuit of pleasure.
People thus consent to a normative convention, the conventionality of which is then forgotten by time, as it transforms into objectified moral truth and as people start treating these norms as a priori
truths. In such a convention, each individual will accept, e.g., that
wrongdoing as such is universally bad, whether done against him
by others or against others by himself, and that he ought, therefore,
72 See also: Ann Lambton, State and Government, 1307, chapter on Fakhr al-Dn
Rz: The Dissociation of Religious and Temporal Power, which examines his
views in Jmi# al-#ulm and relates them to his historical context.
73 See p. 80 ff. supra.
177
to restrain his natural motive to limitlessly seek his own self-interest. Al-Rz indicates that every individual will realise that for such
social order to endure effectively, all or most individuals, including
himself, should adhere to such a convention.
However, on their own, such conventions cannot bring social
order about. The institution and maintenance of order will require
the combination of a legal code, based on a moral convention, with
a recognised sovereign political power that will enforce it on people.
Al-Rz writes in the Ma#lim:
Installing an imm guarantees the prevention of harm that can only
be prevented through it: therefore, it is obligatory (wjib).
The first [premise] stems from our immediate (arr) knowledge
that if a mighty and potent (bi) leader appears in a country, the
condition of that country will become closer to good order (al) than
if this leader did not exist.
As regards the second [premise], since the prevention of harm from
the self (nafs) is obligatory (wjib), whatever is necessary for the prevention of this harm will itself be obligatory.74
Elsewhere, he argues that both law and political authority are necessary for avoiding strife and disorder. The best form of law for
serving this end will be a revealed law (shar#a) that warns wrongdoers of afterlife punishment, which will form a deterrent for both
the mob (awbsh), who will not be completely deterred by judging
bloodshed and anarchy (harj wa-marj) to be morally bad (on prudential
grounds), and the ruler, who will be inclined naturally to oppression. This explains the adth, Islam and political power (suln) are
twin brothers.75
The appointment of a powerful despot will constitute a lesser
evil for each individual than the state of lawlessness, and is thus
prudentially necessary. Therefore, individuals will consent to making a compromise for the sake of the advantage of overall security,
by accepting the authority of a powerful sovereign. In the Arba#n,
al-Rz writes:
If it is said: As there are such advantages in the appointment of
this leader (ra"s), there are also a variety of disadvantages: e.g. [1] if
74
178
chapter four
[subjects] refuse to obey him, corruption will increase;76 [2] he may
become despotic and oppress them; and [3] he may increase taxation77
to strengthen his leadership; so he resorts to extracting money from the
weak and poor.we will say: There is no doubt that such wrongs will
occur. Yet every rational person will know that if the disadvantages
produced from the non-existence of the obeyed leader are compared
to the disadvantages produced from his existence, they will be much
greater. When we find such a dichotomy, consideration should be given
to [the question of which option is] preponderant; for the omission of
a greater good for the sake of a lesser evil is a great evil.78
The question of whether the establishment of the immate is necessary or not was debated from an early stage in Islamic history.
The Khawrij maintained that it is never obligatory, whereas the
Mu#tazil Ab Bakr al-Aamm (d. 225/840) reportedly argued that
only at times of strife does it become obligatory to appoint an imm
for the sake of imposing order. The common Twelver Sh# view
is that God is morally obligated to establish the immate for the
sake of human advantage.79 According to the common Sunni view,
also held by most Mu#tazila and the Zayds, the establishment of
the immate is made obligatory on people by Legal evidence only,
normally consensus. Al-Rz accepts this view in his early kalm
works.80
Yet others were of the view that the establishment of the immate
is known to be obligatory on humans by unaided reason: al-Rz
names some Mu#tazils, viz. al-Ji, Ab l-\usayn al-Khayy (d.
ca. 300/913), Ab l-Qsim al-Ka#b, Ab l-\usayn al-Bar and his
followers.81 These theologians base the obligatoriness of establish-
76
This may imply that when such disobedience occurs, oppression and civil
war may follow.
77 Reading kharj instead of araj. Cf. paraphrase from the Arba#n in Ibn
#Arafa, Mukhtaar, 192.
78 Arba#n, 428; cf. Jmi#, 218. Since good and evil in the statement, The
omission of a greater good for the sake of a lesser evil is a great evil, should, in
my opinion, be understood in terms of benefit and harm, his use of this statement
in this context will not contradict al-Rzs rejection of the original, Neoplatonic
sense thereof (cf. p. 1623 supra).
79 See al-Rzs refutation of al-Sharf al-Murta in this regard (Nihya, fol.
291b295b; Arba#n, 42833; Ma#lim, 135; cf. al-Murta, Dhakhra, 409 ff.).
80 Ul al-dn, fol. 41820; Nihya, fol. 290a291b. Cf. #Abd al-Jabbr, Mughn,
20, 16 ff.
81 Muaal, 574; Arba#n, 4267; Barhn, 2, 199. Cf. al-Ji, Istiqq, 1947;
Lambton, State, 58 ff. I have not found any reference to this view by al-Khayy or
179
al-Ka#b in a source earlier than al-Rz (Josef van Ess cites this view by al-Khayy
from a source that paraphrases al-Rzs Arba#n; see Khayy in EI2, 1163; Ibn
#Arafa, Mukhtaar, 190).
82 Al-Ghazl, Iqtid, 2347; cf. Lambton, State, 110 ff.
83 Al-Frb, $r", 117 ff.
84 Ibn Sn, Shif", Ilhiyyt, 2, 44155; Miriam Galston, Realism and Idealism, esp. 568.
180
chapter four
85
86
87
181
The conditions of leadership are thus not absolute, but are means
to an end. Al-Rz also argues that while the ascetic (nsik) is ultimately the most virtuous person, neither he nor the jurist (faqh) will
be able to rule better than the political expert (syis), who is inferior
in virtue to both of them.91
Epistemological Pessimism
The third section of Dhamm al-ladhdht concerns intellectual pleasure,
which, in contrast to sensory and imaginative pleasures, al-Rz associates with the human good. However, if his expression of pessimism
88
Al-^j (Mawqif, 8, 349) writes that this is the view of the majority (jumhr).
Nihyat, fol. 295b269a; fol. 301a302b (quoted in Ibn #Arafa, Mukhtaar,
1934); cf. Ul al-dn, fol. 4378.
90 Arba#n, 460; cf. Jmi#, 205.
91 Nihya, fol. 302b303b.
89
182
chapter four
92
183
94
184
chapter four
These three arguments highlight the view that the mind is able
to judge some false opinions as constituting apodictic knowledge,
which casts doubt on the very notion and possibility of certainty as
such. If we can trust neither immediate nor discursive knowledge,
we will be unable to affirm any knowledge at all: Reason will be
undermined.97 The sceptical mode that underlies these first three
arguments invokes disagreement (ta#ru) among views taken by various parties, especially philosophers and theologians, pointing to the
poor track record of reason in the history of ideas.98
Al-Rzs fourth argument is taken from the sophists, and is one
that he cites and rejects in earlier works.99 It goes as follows:
If we reflect, contemplate and investigate, and if following this reflection a conviction arises, then our knowledge that this conviction constitutes knowledge cannot be immediate (arr); for truth frequently
turns out to be contrary to it. If it is [said to be] discursive (naar),
it will need another proof; and infinite regress (tasalsul) will follow,
which is absurd.100
Following from the conclusions of the previous argument, this sceptical argument asks for a particular criterion that will enable us to
overcome this general doubt, and to distinguish some of our opinions
as constituting certain knowledge, rather than mere beliefs. However,
any criterion will in turn require further criteria to justify it, which
will lead to infinite regress.
Both sceptical modes, that of interminable disagreement and that
of the infinite regress of proofs, have a long history before and after
al-Rz, and are both referred to by Sextus Empiricus as being the
two most basic sceptical strategies.101 Al-Rz appears here to arrive
judgement (Mulakhkha, fol. 226a; also fol. 216b226a). He later adopts atomist
physics and refutes hylomorphism (e.g. Muaal, 268 ff.; Arba#n, 317), apparently
dedicating a work to this subject (Rislat ithbt al-jawhar al-fard, mentioned in Arba#n,
264; cf. al-Zarkn, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, 70).
97 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 35.
98 This is reminiscent of the notion of the equipollence of opposing proofs (takfu"
al-adilla) (on this, see van Ess, Skepticism, 7). In this context, al-Rz does not seem
to use the latter notion, which implies the affirmation of equivalencesomething
that, as we will see, he may prefer to avoid.
99 Nihya, fol. 13a; fol. 16a; Mulakhkha, fol. 83b; Muaal, 119; Ma#lim, 212;
Khalq, fol. 4a.
100 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 36.
101 Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Scepticism, 1.178-79. Cf. Jonathan Barnes, Some
Ways of Scepticism, 20610.
185
at global scepticism, whereby people only have beliefs, never knowledge, which is defined in apodictic terms.
Having presented these four general arguments, al-Rz supports
his sceptical stance with a specific argument concerning actual controversies among the main metaphysical and theological worldviews.
He outlines the following:
1.
Atheistic views deny the existence of a producer for the physical
world, but explain its existence in one of three ways:
(a)
Physical objects in this world are necessary in themselves.
(b) Their existence is preponderant to their non-existence.
(c)
They are temporally originated. But temporally originated
things do not require a cause.
2.
Some maintain that there is an essentially necessitating First
Cause. They adhere to one of two possible positions:
(a)
The First Cause produces one effect. (Al-Rz specifies
most of the falsifa).
(b) The First Cause may produce more than one effect.
3.
Some maintain that the Creator has choice and considers human
advantage in His acts. They then hold one of the following views
with respect to the problem of evil:
(a)
Two gods exist: a good one, who produces all good, and
an evil one, who produces all evil. (Dualists).
(b) The world came into being when the Soul, out of its ignorance, attached itself to matter. All good in the world is
from God, and all evil is from the Souls ignorance. (Ab
Bakr al-Rz).
(c)
The suffering endured in this world is not bad, since God
will compensate humans for it. (Mu#tazils).
(d) The world is predominantly good, and is the best possible
world. Not to have created it would have been a great evil.
(Al-Ghazl?)
4.
Some maintain that the Creator is a voluntary agent, who
does not consider human advantage in His acts. He sometimes
delivers benefits to humans, sometimes harms. They fall under
two groups:
(a)
Some deny prophecy, the afterlife and religious obligation.
(b) Some affirm prophecy and religious obligation.102
102
186
chapter four
Certainty may thus be attainable, yet rarely and with great difficulty.
In relation to the almost absolute and global scepticism of the first
four arguments in this section of Dhamm al-ladhdht, the scepticism
expressed here appears qualified and restricted. Al-Rz then writes,
in conclusion to Dhamm al-ladhdht:
103
104
105
187
106 Nihyat aqdm al-#uql #iql. Interestingly, this line echoes two kalm titlesalRzs own Nihyat al-#uql, and al-Shahrastns Nihyat al-aqdman apparently
symbolic pun.
107 Meter: awl. Cf. the following Persian quatrain attributed to him (quoted in
translation by Seyyed H. Nasr, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, 653, without reference):
188
chapter four
Beneficent is established on the Throne,111 His saying, They fear
their Lord above them,112 and His saying, Unto Him good words
ascend.113 And I read, on that all is from God, His saying, Say,
all is from God,114 and, on exalting Him above what is inappropriate, His saying, Whatever of good befalls you, it is from God; and
whatever of ill befalls you, it is from thyself.115 And so forth, by this
same rule (qnn).
I say, from the depth of my heart, and the inmost of my soul: I
confirm that all that is most perfect, most virtuous, greatest and most
glorious pertains to You, and that You are exalted above all that involves
defect or imperfection. I confirm that my mind and comprehension
fall short of attaining the true reality of a single atom of the atoms of
Your creatures. And I confirm that I have failed to praise You with
what befits You. For eulogies are of either of two types; they either
expound attributes of majesty (jall), which is exalting God above what
is inappropriate, or expound attributes of beneficence (ikrm), which
is attributing to God His being the creator of this world. Yet the first
involves ungraciousness in some respects, for if a man tells a king,
You are not blind, deaf, or leprous, he will deserve reprimand and
confinement. As for the second, it involves ungraciousness; for all the
perfections of creatures are imperfections in relation to the Creators
perfection; hence, expounding the Creators perfection using relative
attributes that relate [Him] to creatures involves ungraciousness.
O, Lord of might! I admit that I am incapable of praising You
except in either of these two ways! And I admit that neither befit Your
majesty and might. Yet I am as though excusable; for I know naught
but this, and I am unable to find anything superior to it!116
The beginning of this statement is by far the most explicitly pessimistic statement to be found anywhere in al-Rzs writings, and
is among the most extreme expressions of pessimism that can be
found in medieval Arabic prose. It remains surprising even as a
conclusion to the pessimistic trend throughout Dhamm al-ladhdht.
And indeed, the interest of this statement, which clearly expresses
a genuine sentiment and sincere conviction of its author in one of
his latest texts, made parts of it among the most frequently quoted
pieces of his writings.
111
112
113
114
115
116
Qur. 20:5.
Qur. 16:50.
Qur. 35:10.
Qur. 4:78.
Qur. 4:79.
Dhamm al-ladhdht, 423.
189
117
Malib, 1, 3764.
190
chapter four
118 On this distinction between #ilm and ma#rifa, cf. al-Tahnaw, Kashshf, Ma#rifa;
Ma#rifa, EI2.
119 Malib, 1, 416.
120 Cf. p. 1167 supra.
121 E.g. Risla f l-nafs, fol. 2a.
122 Asrr al-tanzl, 1412; cf. San", \adqat al-aqqa, 63; M. Stephensons translation, 4.
191
perplexity and bewilderment and in [having to] accept what is probable and apt.
This induction shows that, in its attempt to understand the most evident
objects of knowledge, the mind will culminate in utter perplexity and
bewilderment (ma al-ayra wa-l-dahsha) and will have to accept what
is probable and apt. So how do you reckon the mind will fare when it
[attempts] to ascend to the gates of Gods greatness, and when it tries
to delve into investigations of the nature of His [attributes]!123
123
192
chapter four
127
If we say: His being knowing and powerful are two positive items, distinct from
[His] essence, Ab Hshim [al-Jubb"] will say: Being knowing (#limiyya) and
being powerful (qdiriyya) cannot be said to be existent or non-existent, knowable
or unknowable. Most sensible men agree on that his saying is false.
For, necessarily, every assertion has to be preceded by conception. So, if these
two attributes are not conceived, it will not be possible to maintain that both are
193
Minds fall short of knowing Him, and perceptions do not reach Him.
Rather, the highest aim [for reason] is that if we perceive the meaning
of perfection and imperfection in relation to ourselves, ... we will
understand the meaning of perfection and imperfection as such.
For the unconditional [conception] (mulaq) is part of the essence of
the conditional (muqayyad) [conception]. In this way, the meaning of
perfection and imperfection may be perceived. If we perceive this
meaning, we may accept to affirm the designation perfect with respect
to [God], provided that we purge this designation of all concomitants
associated to it when it applies to us.
Most people will have only this much knowledge of [Gods] majesty. With this explanation, it becomes clear that human minds come
to achieve nothing but these general items of knowledge, which are
affirmed only according to what is most probable and apt, but not
in detail.133
The scepticism that al-Rz reaches in the Malib finds expression in his numerous references to bewilderment and perplexity
(al-ayra wa-l-dahsha).134 Though his sceptical stance, viewed within
the history of ideas generally, will appear rather moderate, it is
indeed a radical scepticism in the context of kalm and falsafa. In
the wider Islamic context, it was generally seen that no less than
knowledge, defined in terms of certainty (qa#, yaqn), should be
contented with in theological questions, to the exclusion of mere
belief and presumption (ann), which contain an element of doubt
(shakk, shubha).135 Al-Tahnaw, for example, records the common
view that doubt is a subspecies of ignorance (jahl).136 Those who
favoured a discursive approach did so with the conviction that it
does provide certainty. Thus, in his earlier works, al-Rz writes,
with reference to metaphysics, that affirming what is most prob-
194
chapter four
137
Mabith, 2, 482.
In earlier works, al-Rz refutes these alternative approaches in favour of theological and metaphysical reflection (Nihya, fol. 19b22b; Muaal, 122; 1267).
139 Gisela Striker, Sceptical Strategies, 54; cf. Charlotte Stough, Greek Skepticism,
4.
138
195
Now that these various positions have been summarised in this manner,
and that the praiseworthy and blameworthy aspects of each have become
evident, at this point those who are perplexed and bewildered (ab
al-ayra wa-l-dahsha) will say: These proofs are not clear and strong
enough to dispel doubt (shakk), preclude excuses and enlighten the
mind with their strength and vividness. Rather, each betrays a degree
of obscurity. One who is merciful and magnanimous should excuse
one who errs in such defiles.140
196
chapter four
142
197
143
198
chapter four
al-Tawd (Imt#, 1, 38; cf. Roshdi Rashed, Qh vs. Aristotle, 9) refers to the
aversion that some contemporaries from both groupsphysicians and mathematicianshad towards metaphysics: This one studies illness and health, disease and
medicine, and that one examines the sun and the moon. Yet none of them will
have anything to say on soul, intellect or deity, as though these [subjects] were
forbidden to them, or blameworthy among them.
It is possible that al-Rz, who wrote at least two major works on medicine, was
inspired also by this metaphysical scepticism propounded by physicians, which he
must have come across (although we have found no evidence in his works to confirm
this influence). For instance, in On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato (5779), which
al-Rz read (cf. Nafs, 74), Galen notes that whereas one finds many interminable
disagreements among philosophers, disagreements among physicians are often
resolved: In philosophy it is not surprising that most disagreements have not been
resolved, as the matters it deals with cannot be clearly judged by an empirical test,
and therefore some say that the universe did not have a beginning, others that it
had, and again some say that there is nothing outside surrounding it, others that
there is something, and of the latter, some say that what surrounds it is a void that
has no substance in it, others that it is surrounded by other universes numerous
beyond calculation, so that their number reaches to infinity. Such disagreement
cannot be settled by clear sense-perception. But the case is not the same when a
disagreement arises among physicians about the benefit or harm of remedies applied
to bodies; physicians, at least, can judge by empirical test which of them is helpful
and which is harmful. (Cf. J. Barnes, Some Ways of Scepticism, 206).
148 Mulakhkha, fol. 83b.
149 Malib, 1, 41.
150 For sources on ancient sceptical influences on Islamic thought generally,
see: D. Gutas, Pre-Plotinian Philosophy, 4963.
199
151
200
chapter four
ing (dhikr) God, both inwardly and outwardly, his soul will witness,
directly, divine illumination and knowledge. These are stations that
man will not fathom in detail (#al sabl al-tafl) unless he attains
them.155 Certainty, in other words, may only be reached through the
method of spiritual discipline (arqat al-tafiya wa-l-riya), leading to
spiritual perfection, rather than the discursive method, the method
of reflection and inference (arqat al-naar wa-l-istidll). Nonetheless, proficiency in both paths will allow one to critically assess the
knowledge and stations that he arrives at, which will enable him to
recognise pitfalls along the spiritual path, such as believing that he
has arrived at the end of the path when experiencing very powerful
and unfamiliar states and revelations.156
Al-Rzs metaphysical scepticism, as we saw, rests partly on the
following line of reasoning, in relation to the epistemic limitations
of man: (1) conceptions cannot be acquired; (2) the conceptions
that humans ordinarily perceive fall into certain mundane types of
essences; (3) the range of meaningful statements of assertion is determined by the range of their constituent perceived conceptions; (4)
therefore, statements of assertion that humans can ordinarily make
will be mundane and can refer to supra-mundane items only in a
very general sense. Therefore, the inability to attain supra-mundane
knowledge is not essential to the soul itself, but is due to an accidental limitation in its range of perception, which is determined by the
nature of its association with the physical body. While the soul cannot attain supra-mundane knowledge discursively, it is, in principle,
capable of direct supra-mundane perception, when its attachment
to the body loosens. This is the only way for the soul to attain true
theoretical perfection.
Al-Rz thus concludes that the method of spiritual discipline
is the superior alternative to kalm and falsafa, and the solution to
epistemological pessimism and utter despair. How then should we
understand his numerous statements, in his later writings, that what
he refers to as the method (arqa) of the Qur"n should be regarded
as the superior alternative to kalm and falsafa? He constantly describes
this method as one that involves both the abandonment of delving
deeply (ta#ammuq) into theoretical complications and subtleties, and
155
156
Malib, 1, 545.
Malib, 1, 589; cf. Tafsr, 21, 14950.
201
The same view also appears in Book One of the Malib, where
he states, Whoever abandons obstinacy and experiences the like
of my experience will realise that truth is as I have described.159
But what is the method of the Qur"n? And in what way is it a
superior alternative?
For this, we need to revisit al-Rzs later theory of prophecy.
Revelation, he argues, will have spiritually transformative features
in its style and content that are ideal for perfecting human souls.
For instance, the method of revealed religions generally, and Islam
in particular, is to attribute all perfections to God and to exhort
people to proclaim His greatness to the maximum extentmainly by
affirming attributes of majesty (jall) and beneficence (ikrm)while
avoiding intricate theological problems, which may cause confusion
in peoples minds. It will then prohibit believers from delving deeply
into theological details of the various aspects of Gods greatness and
divinity, some of which may appear irreconcilable. These and other
transformative features of prophecy correspond to al-Rzs description of the method of the Qur"n.160 This is described in his Asrr
al-tanzl, where he comments on Qur. 7:545, as follows:
157
202
chapter four
His saying, Verily, His are the creation and the command, contains
a remarkable secret and a profound wisdom; namely, that if you witness signs of [divine] governance and design in the various parts of
the heavens, the planets and the earth, your heart will desire to know
the aspects of wisdom in each one of them in detail (#al sabl al-tafl).
It will then be said to you: Halt at your level, do not venture beyond
your limits, nor plunge your mind into an endless ocean, nor set off
to surmount a summit-less mountain, nor desire to fathom what is
above your understanding, imagination, mind and soul! You are not
one of those who could attain these illuminations. Rather, admit your
incapacity, humility, and shortcoming, and proclaim the perfect majesty
and ultimate greatness of the Creator of these beings summarily (#al
sabl al-ijml); and say: Verily, His are creation, command, wisdom,
might, exaltedness, dominion and greatness, blessed be God, the Lord of
the worlds, He who governs all bodies, souls, higher beings and lower
beings! Having abandoned wading into those details and recognised
this greatness summarily, at this stage, you should return to yourself
and consider your incapacity and shortcoming. Then busy yourself
with prayer and supplication.
Herein lies the ultimate level attainable by the spiritually advanced
ones (iddqn) and the acme of the thoughts of knowers (#rif), beyond
which minds cannot venture. ... To this God, exalted, alludes towards
the end of this verse in His saying: Supplicate your Lord humbly
and secretly.
How beautiful these pointers (talw), contained in the great Qur"n,
are! ... No method (arq) occurs to the mind or imagination of this
humble person (miskn), who is the author of the present book, which
is better, more advantageous or more attractive (ajdhab) for human
souls and intellects towards the presence of Him who is Holy, One
and Everlasting, than these divine expositions and lofty secrets!161
161 Asrr al-tanzl, 3723; cf. 376. The same points, he goes on to add, are
highlighted in Qur. 3:1901.
203
204
chapter four
appendix
205
APPENDIX
... .
End:
% ( '
-
@ AB
.C D
A'
.D
206
appendix
M P QD .@(
.
T
U @ D %D
CD
... Z . P .D \ D
End:
. CD
D .@ P ...
.(
. @ AB % a(
P c@ ' P .
g\ D
D@
L AB
P D D
... :
2
3
appendix
207
End:
C D
D .@ P ...
.
4. Mar#ash-Najaf Library 286(26) (fol. 247b255b):4
Title: Taqr al-ladhdht.
Dimensions: 18 27.5; 11 13.5 cm. 27 lines.
Dated: 1072 A.H. (1662).
Copyist: Shh Murd Farhn.5
Handwriting: nasta#lq.
Beginning:
M P QD .@(
.
T
U @ D %D
CD
... Z . P .D \ D
End:
. CD
D .@ P ...
. @ AB % a(
5. The British Library, I.O. (India Office Library) Islamic
3832 (fol. 85b95b):6
Title: Kitb Taqr al-ladhdht.
Dimensions: 27.7 14.8; 19.5 8.5 cm. 21 lines.
Dated: 1063 A.H. (1653).
Handwriting: exquisite nasta#lq.
208
appendix
Beginning:
D M % P P ( M AB(
.%D %D %D %a mD P
M P QD .@(
.
T
U @ D %D
CD
... Z . P .D \ D
End:
7
8
appendix
209
The Title
The epistle is given the following titles in manuscripts and later external
references:
Dhamm ladhdht al-duny (Censure of the Pleasures of This World).9
Risla f Dhamm al-duny (Censure of This World).10
Taqr al-ladhdht (Degrading Pleasures).11
Risla f l-ladhdht al-malba f l-duny (On the Pleasures Sought in
This World).12
5. Aqsm al-ladhdht (Divisions of Pleasure).13
1.
2.
3.
4.
The fourth and fifth titles appear to be taken directly from the epistles
introduction and describe its contents superficially. In my opinion, the
first title appears most authentic. It describes the works main parts
and conclusions, without being simply drawn from its introduction.
It also agrees with the authors description of the second section as
the section on the censure (dhamm) of imaginary pleasures, in his
final note in the work, preserved only in the Berlin MS. The second
title seems to be a shortened version of the first.
Finally, al-Rz refers to the work loosely both as a book (kitb)
and as an epistle (risla).14
9
10
29.
11 The Princeton MS; the British Library MS; and the Mar#ash-Najaf 286 MS.
All, however, share a common source.
12 The Kabul MS catalogue entry.
13 Ibn Taymiyya (e.g. Dar", 1, 159) and Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya (Ijtim#, 120).
However, both almost certainly used the same manuscript.
14 Dhamm al-ladhdht, 3; 44.
210
appendix
211
appendix
@ ' %
AB
appendix
212
@ o D o
D
D
D D D P D ~ D .o
P~
D o D
D \ .D
D .
\ . DP \ g
@oP
D
P
@
@ . Q P M%
\D @D
T \D
D @ U
D.
D
P Z P % M
p .
PD m \ : % M~ Q @P M Q .
D wDPD . %
Do %
D % D wPD [P :] . %
: .
: .
@( D . Q P M
" :L .
T\D
%DD @ U
CD
D".
. L
B M :Qo @ .
213
appendix
D % D w .
M (.
.
o DP M m \ ~ %
PD U
\ g D
D~
\' D
o %D D '
D .'
D
D % % \g
B@D
D %D o ~ w@
.
( P :
D @
D
D M : %D [ :] m
D %a.%
D M : %D Q D'
D.
D m % a
D M : %D Q D
D w m % D.Q
D mP w@ .
" % D" .
" % D w PD % D "%
.L
: .
: L @.
: .
.
@ :L .
.L
appendix
214
:D M %
m P ] [( : @ M Q.
Ps o D - .Q
P o \
P . (
Do
'D m m
@
o M g\ w (D . m P (
\( \ .m m P
a
( D
@
@ @ '
( ] [P :L o
@ A
( o U @ P PD .@
\ ' m P \o g @
@ .
D m P o L \ @
D m
M D ~C~
wD
:L .
: .
:L (.
: .
:L PD.
:L .U
: .
' :L ~.
.
. L
:L ~ M~ wD .
215
appendix
oP %
"P @o M
C%
D . .:
D m
D
D ."% A
M o
P .
wD @DD . o
D - o
%
D [P :] .%'
m P m M %
w U
U
M w U D DPD .~o'
(D \ M
o D M @D
C U ] [ : ~ D . m o
w D @D o M % M . D
D .
\ g % @ M Q w Q
D .
D w Q D
D Qw D D .
PD M m m \ :D wD ww
Do@P '\ MP a D m oDw@
:L ~.
.
: .
.
: .m
D :L .
" w "Q .L
:L .
:L : ..QwD
: .
: .
appendix
216
% g\
%.
P \" :m a .
D ". m P @P g\ Q M
mP
Q \ P DD w
B.
D P m \" : D @D
D ."% P U
D%o
%
P mD P
\ P ] [( :D % D %
B.
D % B Q o
P M~ %a
B"D . P U
P m P mD~ %
D%o \ m P m@' @ BD
%a
@o M
. w
@
:L .
:L @.Q
: D w.
: .
.L
:L .
:L .
: .
:L .
" "w . L
217
appendix
~ D w M w P D .
D\ %a P
D
P P M
P ~ B D PD . w
%a
D [ :] %o
m P~ P M
P D o D' M.
'\D m D mP M (
P .s M m P m~ D'D.
D M - m P m P \ P mPD B
D .
D M : ( P .ms m P :~
P
% M
\D %
P
\o g . :- P m m\D
%
\ % P ] [P :
Q a .
~ D~.
D m
P
\ : @P m P m P m PD U g\ U
m'~ P D m ~ P m
.
:L D .
M" "m .
D : .m
:L .
:L D.-
.
: '.
appendix
218
'~
PD .
P PD . U
m P
\ g .P @P P ~ P PD o m
o o
P PD
P ~ D %\ %
.
w @ Q
@D
M
P m P c
@ o ' m m
'
(oD ' (
@ M A D P '
w
w@ B o ] [P :L @ Q
D \
.
.@ @
w@ B o '
D . (
D
( ' w
@ Q Q
' w@ o
@.o
\ o ~ DD'D .
P ~ %
: '.
P : .
: m ...o m.
: .
.M :
: .m
' : .
.L
: L .
: @.M Q
@.
:
219
appendix
% P M
%
m P~ P
] [( : \ o DD . :'\ m
(
o@P w D @ '
@ D P ]\ [ : .%
'\ Q@ o D Q @D
D . m \ P m'~ P
m P a L" :~ P Q c Q D( D."
'D
P ~ \ % o .
M m( ' A~ m P P
Q BP wPD c Q
D PPD c . m Q Q
D .
P mP c @ Qo
@D g\ U
@ g\
.L
' : .
:L ( .
:L .
.P:
' :L .
.
:L D . :.
: .m
:L .
D :L P.
" m Q Q D " .L
.
.L
appendix
220
@D m
\ m Q m
@ g\ m
P .
@D Qo
\ g
D D . @
. P \ gP w D Q
D P PD m B P '\D . @ Q
Q \ M '\D .m
M D @
Q M M'\D .
][P :
D @ . m P
\P m DD ' m D Q
Qo
@ U c . .
M mP m~ % 'D P
@ % @ . Q
\ Q
. m m
P Q [( :L]
\ \' D MD .
' m P M
D D
@.
P M
w
: .
" @" . L
: L .
: .
.m :L
:L .w
: mP@.
: .
: .
: .Q@D
:L % @.Q
: .
221
appendix
D m P mm
@D mP o ] g\ [ :'D .
m PQ
\ ' m DP
% [email protected]
D w
PD m \ U '\ m D
D(
w M D Q Q
( a ~ .
: .
:L .
: .
" D \" .
M : .
: \.m
.
D" m ... m@" .
B M :Qo@.
:L w.
appendix
222
\ Q%
~ m P %~ %
@'D .Q
m P~ M Q m PD \
P ~ D Q o P U
P A
P@D m P
\D . \ P .
:
P
w c
mP
D(D
PD Q P mP \ gD .m A
P P w m ~ wD . m p
m P
D ~ \D w m
p m P D o %o m
( D m M Q mD~ 'D .w
P ]P [P :L w.m
Qo m~ w
~ PD .w U~
\
\ m Q
\ Q
%o M Q .w
D \ [ :] Q D P@ U
: .
:L .
: .
.
: .
:L .
.L
B M .mP :Qo
:L Q.
.
223
appendix
D '
m P~ % \
@ Q .
~
% @ Q 'D .
P ] [P :
D
D %aD % .%o m a \
D
\ g .' o DD
D.%a
%
P
B\ '%
D
m P \' M \ gD w@
\ PD M Q
D w .' ( \ gD w@ o
D Q o @\DD . P \ Q \B
DP %
.% . m P~ \ mP m
\ m
% M D @.Q
M m ~ : w
\
p w ~ P . \ a Q 'D
\' \ D U a M D ~DD
: @.Q
" " .L
' : .
' : .
: D %a.%
.D :L
.L M
" ~ P \" .
:L .~D
appendix
224
D %D % D D D m BD U.
P \' \ M D P m D(PD \ D
BD U
D mDo D mD P B QD .
m Pp Q Q m~ .
PD \ a Q D ~[( :] .
\ :D
m P P
P P D D'D .w
\ ][ :
a m~ .%
D m \ :-
@
L \ M D~ ] [( :L P D .L
\ \@ D \@ .
\
P .
\ w m P % D P
'
Q a \ .
M m ~ mP P : Q
Q D . \ M D gD
:L D ~D~.
D : .
.L
.L
.
" " .L
.
B M .mP :Qo
: .Q
P : .
225
appendix
' .
.'
B m P m ~ B Q m .
D m L m \" :m @ g Q P w
oDPD P M D ."w m P w D
' PD . w
D c ' D '\D .
: Q Q a D~:
m P D~ Q \ DP M
D .Q
D .'
[P :] m P - ~ Q \ .' @
\ g wA .Q
D m P Q M Q Q .
m P~ Q Q a ~ .%
m P D~ Q
PD Q Q a D~ .
\ D M D PD . ~
D : : ..
.L
.m :L
: .
.'D : L
: .
. L
: .%
.
DP : .
: .
:L .
appendix
226
% PD . ~
D mD o w
D .m
D Q . ] [ :
Dw
D
\
m A
. ' m P m .
PD 'D . m
\ mm P
D w
D A D Q DP
.
DD % Mw
D'[P :L] m
D DP D D a P D
DP
. ' p m P w Q ~
D p w .%
Q
PD U~ Q D . ] M [( :
\ g
PD .% U D - D' PD U PD .
% D( D w.
m P D M %~ %
: .
: .
:L .m
.
D :L D D : .a P D .a
D :L .
: .Q
: .Q
D :L .%
227
appendix
. ~ \ !% \ m
D a QD .a m P P c
D D P . BP
M Q
.
' m P~ % Q \ g.%
M mP m~ % Q a'D : mP
% ( Q a D \
P . m P m
'D
mP a
m \ : m
p M % '\D
\ ' a U@ o M.
P U
\cP@ '\D .
\' @ cP U o @ ~C
% D .
\D . p M
U U
Q
m P
] @ D o [ : P %o PD .
:L .
.
D :L .
D : .
.L
: .m
" " . L
.
.
M : .%
: .o
" . M @ "~C .L
appendix
228
BD D '\ m P
\ g .' @ B 'D c '\D . m
'~ D w .
D ] [P : A c Q C @D m
' @ %o . w
\ m\D .@
P . m m U
' w
D @ o .
m\D .
m P mPD mP U M D D.
( o D ] [( :L.~ D
PD \ \'
'D M a.a
m P P DD PD .m
D Q a D . m P M @o D
.
.mP :
' : .
: .%o
D : .
:L .
.
: L .m
.'D :L
: L D.
.L
" " B. M Q
229
appendix
\ g .o m P P \ @D
DD .% P.
:- M %
D Q D~
mP D P
D m P M D .
D aD . mP -
\
P M
.
~ D %
M :D m P m (
D D~.
mP m mPD a m
m P :
P
~ @ D
D'D . m m m @o
P : .
D" P" .L
. L
: .
P : s.
: L a"D . "a .
P : .
. L
: .
: .
.
appendix
230
D
D .
a
@D a
D
D
a ] [( :
P mP m
. m P
D M [ :] mPD ~a ~a mPm
~a
@ UD U '\D . m M
m \ ' PD .m
~ M m
\ \ MD '\D . m m
M PD p P D(
\ M m oD \D '\D . m m
M ( M
P D \ M
' c
oD M Q m P
D
' .
D( A
MD \ M m
.
D m m M
: .
:L .
.
.L
.L
D : L .
.
.L
M D a "".
.
:L .
231
appendix
DD m
D U( B.
m" : @ m \" : m M \
m
' m"D
(DP m \ : D m@ \ ] [P :L m
D QP P .s mP C '
. P DQ
D@ D P L Q D . mP [P :] -
D g\ Q \
. D\ .Q \m
P \ M P m PD
M \ ~a mP m D
] g\ [ : D . @~.
M m D : m P @ Q '
D m U
:L D : . D.
:L .
: .
: .
:L D@.D
' : .
:L (D : .(.
D : .-
.L
.L
.
appendix
232
@ a D@ Q ~
D
D w D
~ \ . \ m
D@ D .
: B D@ Qm
\'
D Q DQo m
D .' 'DD .
'\D ooB \D @ DP a PD U
U m ~ .
m P M D B
P DB
D . m ~B@%
' A D '
D
D@P Q m'~ P '\D .c m m
oB o P PDc m '
P A.c
] m P [( : M \ P
w
D 'D . \ m m
m P m\D . B m'~
" ~ " .
:L .
.L
: .
'\D" " .L
oB :L .o
D : .m
D : .
.' :
:L .
233
appendix
Pc m B Pc m w '
P .c
D .
m P P D
D m @ Q Q
'\D .
D mP
DP :
\ g
C
@ cP
DP
C ~
'D . m
] [( :L M m
@D .
m mo U ~a ~D%
D(
m o mD U PD .U m '
] [ :P . P m ~D % m m mo U~a
D ~ D % PD . Q @D P
(
:L
" m w ' P "c .
D : .
: .
: .a
@
@ )o) (/ % m
@(D . o
"(.
"@ cP
:L .
: L .a
: L .a
.L
: .
appendix
234
g\ a D .~
\ ~ \'
@ D
PD . m P~
P
m m m m U o
.D m P m moU
@
' B
@.
a ~D%
D(
PD m P m m o mD U P'D U m
D m
' QD @
@ Q U ] [P : . m~ o
. m P
D D' c
P DP . DB
D .
D D U ~a
M m m \ : w P m
MP D B\ M P D .
a P w U \ M
P .% m P
M
'
P w
D c \\ g \D D .
@
M L
D m P m' A . mPQ
.L
. M
:L .
.D : L
p :.
p :.
.
@ : .
: .
' :L ~.
235
appendix
m M ~
P D B .Q
\ M m m
Q
P \\ g m
.
M m ( m P \ m mPP m
DP ~a mD U DP ~a m
P .~a mm
P ~a P ~a D .a
@ \ M :] .
[ m' m m D U
D w\ M m B\D @ mD.
m\D ' m m \B
w
\ w ] [( :
P .ms ]P [P :L \P m
~'D . w M %D o.
DP - \ m D ~ \P g a
.L
D :L .
: D .M "" \ \ g M
.
" m
P \\ g m" .L
:L ~ ( MD . L "(" "."%
.
: L D .m .
" mP m "~a .L
: L D.
: .
appendix
236
D U D .
mPDm
~ .
PD \' mD U ~a
D
D D '\D .
D .
w m ~ \ M \D @ P P PD
' A U'D . m@ Q
w M % U D D @ Q
o w U % Dm ' a U
' m a U M.
P
\ p D ."% w
A
B.o
m P m ~ D
mP
.L
mPD" "m .L
.m\ :
D : ~D.
.L
: .
: .a
.
.
: .
:L .w
237
appendix
B DP DP UDD . m Pp %
% D .m m P~ Q
D PD.
m
] M [P : m ~ Q m P
\ m mP M m M DP DP Q m U . mM m
D Q P QD m\D . M m MD aQ
P P m ~ a ] [ :
D D .w m
mP PD m P D \ U PD a
M . P PD
P DPD c PD . \ m m mU
: D :L . DD.
.L
.
: .
" % D m mP~ Q " .L
.
.
.
"M" .
:L D.
.L
: L .Q
.
.
appendix
238
D .~ Q D
D Q m
'\D . m m P . m P
m
D D.m
] [( :L m P@ m %
@
\ m D P
P PD c
D . m \" :@ Q
a \ \ m@ Q a @
@ Q
a
D % PD . @ Qo
P
@ ".
Q o
\' : % ~ % \
@
D @ \ DP MD.
: Q ~D :L .D QD .
: .
D : L .
:L : .
.
. L
.L
: @ .
@ : . m
@ : . m
: .
:L .
D" @ " .L
: .
B P :L M Qo M .D
239
appendix
@
P D [( M D D w
'
' '\ D . ' D
p
a U C w . m P m
D %D@ '~ \ m M D .
C UD D D .Qo ' D
D Q . m P w \g
M P
o .
D m P '\ m (
' \ mP g a U D . m P@ Q
D
D .% w a ] [ :m
.%
\' m \ : \' \ gD QDo
D QwD~ QD P
m P a
D D ~o P] .[ P
\ g
. L
.L
: '.
: L p.
: '.
: .
: ~.
. L M
: .%
D :L ..Qo
. L
: .
appendix
240
D ~D D M U@Q
D M m@ Q ~ D@ % QD ~
D pD .Q m~ .
\ g D D w m D oD .QD %@Q
' .
M
~ ' D .
@ D .
[P :] -D . M
~
LD oQD
D \ g
DD QwD UP M @ B D w
\ @ ] [P :L . P M P
P om
P M P
D '\D .
w ~ \ M a M DP .
(
m P \ m mP ( D a
\ g\ aa \D mP (
D" D ~o P D ~"
.L
D : .
.
.L
: L .
: .
: .L .
\D :L .
.
.L
\ : :L ..
.
241
appendix
MD .
D D
D
C % P .Qa
CDP .% m P
mP (
D @ U
L D a P~
\ P @ mD .D m P
'\ L ~ PD~ D \
D
@D.
P L \ \ mD D w@B D
D P \' a@ ] [ :D oD .~
Q .
( \ g\ a a
PD D - mP
CP .% \ m P g\ a
] [( : \
P ' M U .
Q a D'
\D \ a M
@ ' a U QD.Q
D
: .
D :L .
: .
:L D.
:L .
:L .
D : L .
:L .
: .
.
:L aD : . \ a.
appendix
242
P \"D . m P@ D A \
D " :
Qo
a a oD U a
. M
@D . @ % Qo ' a U M U .QD m P
P - Z ( D %a m
@.
M ~ Q D : m P \ m mP
p D \D mP DD .
D D @ D @
@ P . B
'D . B m m U D m
o
. m @
.'
D PD . [( :L] U m m
M . \'
M
P D [P :] L P
M m D Qac
%D Q m
m
% o \ g M %Q
D % . \ a U
P . \'
:L .
. L
.
: ( .
: L .
.
:L .
:L .
: .
: L .
243
appendix
D M Q B U . m P
D .
D Q m ] [ :
P
PD D - P U
\ @ U '\D .% m m
\@ 'D ( . a
(.
a P D~
\ \ m( \
( .( D D D DP w \
a P \' m m o a
~a
m U .
\w
D m PD m m .m
.' mD
p P PD
D m .' D ( ~
: L.
.L
:L .%
D .
" "m .
.
:L .
@ : .
: .a
:L .
:L .
: ' m.
.'\ :
D AP U .~D
D :~ .
appendix
@D
P PD .
(.
D m P
D L U ]D [( : U
D '\D . m @ Q
P( a
D D QDPD .
D '\D . m p @ Q
A .
DD .w Q
@( D P
m
D.
D m P \ m mP M U D
D DP .
D D
D D w mDD
D % P .% ] [P :L
D P U .w m \ mP
\D mP P .~a [ :] D
m
PD . w \ m ~a
DD ww 'D
D : .
.
:L .
: L .
" A " .
: D a.
. L M
: .
.
.mDo :
:L @.
\ D~w
244
245
appendix
m
P m D
PD . D - w D D U
w C 'D . \ g D DD
D % m \ .% \ m m m
D % m\D .%o@ m U m
DD .% @ cP @
@
D D~ " : ! \ m m\D [P :] %
".
M m ~ mP Q :~ Q
M Q DP D D . mw
( P m' Pc
PD m mP m m@
D
@DD % % U
'~
D : .m
D : .
: .
p : D . : M(.
. L
B : M Qo' .
:L : . P D.
.L
:L '~.
:L .
D : D.%
: .
appendix
246
m D . ' m P
m
'D . m
D
P m DD oD %
' @
%
D .
PD D - mP :~ M Q a D
Q m\ : m m P M
m~
% '\ D
D
D
%o P c~
P ~ P U .
M ~ mP Q : \ m mPm
@ U DP a MD .m
P P .%
D
D D mP@ m U : \ ] [ :m
" : "[email protected]
:L .
:L .m
D : L D o.
" "% :L . .%
. L
.L
:L .m
.L
.L
: .Qo@\ m
: @.Qo
247
appendix
] [( :L % P %o .
m P [( :] %o P m
P D D D w
. P P
\ g
\ mP m DP Ds P .
@ m \ g \ g
m
gDP PD UD . ~ m\D .
\ \ M @ PD .Q P U
: @.%o
: L .
: .
.m :L
: L .
.%
:L
: .m
: .m
: L .
.
: .
:L .
.
appendix
248
' m
DD a P D.
@ ~ P U .
D
M D : P \
\ ( DD . m
P
PD mDo D mm \ @
@ D D . mPD
P\" :
D M m ] [P : Q
D@'D :Q m P \ Q D '\D .
] g\ [ : 'D .a \
D m
m
D .a
P .
a
D \ D Qa
.
:L .
: .@D
: .
.L
. L
.L
.
:L .m
:L .
:L .
249
appendix
D ~ ' D U . PD \ g
U DD A
D a ! a
o '\ . \ g
o \ @
' @ M P M
. ]@ [P :L DD \
MD D
\D (D
D M
D.
m P \ mP m
Q
\D mP m U
MD .U
D
a
D P \' D ~
C P .%
M D mDo D \ mD . \'
@ ' U D D( .
PD D - mP m U Q
D :L .
.L
D : .
D : L .
:L @.
M :L D D D D(.
B DD . M Q
: .D Q
.
:L ~ .D
D : .
: (.
appendix
250
P \' ~ D D PD . \ m\" :
a [( :]
"
. P m M m
D@~ a
DQ @D m . m P U
D
P P ( P P .
A p P M
m P : \ mP
D P
D \D mP
P .
( D . m\" :
D
PD - P U
D M 'D
D ~
w @'D .Q P U P
.%
m P m P -\" :
: .
:L .~D
.
.
: m D.gDP Q
@. M Q
.L
D"
P P( P P" D .
.
.L
:L .
D : .L.
251
appendix
P p
%"D . m
%! P
.
D
" : m P~ M D Q\ . \ m
%
. P QPD c
PPD c.
D @
.
D( w
:
M %
m P \ \D D P .
\ QD . [( :L] m
P
Q \ o
.
~ [P :] Q gDPD . P m P
.
.
: .
.L
:L .
.
:L ( : . (.
: .
D :L .
252
appendix
Q \
c
@ .
PD \ mP m DP a P .
( ~a D . m U ~a m
@
' P D .a % @Q
P : D DD % D
@P M
.
D :D D P D . D A
@ ' ( !L
\ g Q! D A
@ '
D % DP
D
m
DD .% A
D ~ \pD P [ :] . p D~.
]~ p[
D
DP w
\ m
m \ \' o \
D
\ w D DP Q m
D
: L .
\ : .
B : M Qo.A
.L
B : M Qo.
: L .D
253
appendix
\D w D .
' D @ P U \
D '\D
w
m P '\ %
D P U '\D . @Q
\ w
Z
D
PD U .
'\ D :
m U U m DD
PD [( :] mP B .m
D mP m m P
DP m P
'.
" Q " M
'\ D :~ w
P m
mPD
DD D mP
P " "U m
PD . m P c A
- DD U U m P~ w
% D \
P M
U m P M .
\ w D P U"
Z
" '\D D
.L
:L .
. L
: .L.
.D :L
:L .
.
: L .
: .
:L .A
: .
appendix
254
Po
D m P
\ m
D m P ]:L
D .
D P U
Po D . mP m \" :
D Q
[P
D . \D .
"
mP\" :s D cQ \ \ m
M
D Q %
."w
m P [ :] A
mP U
'\D .w m
m a
M '\D .% m
p .
' " :
m" : \
M .Q m m
.
]P [P : c
w
m\D . m
.L
: .
: .
\ : \ : .s.
: .
:L .
.L
: '.
.L
: .
255
appendix
\ c M @
m a@~
.o :
D m
m P
.
a \D .
: m
D m .~o
C
'\D m a DP m m C M
D .% m
U w .P
m m@D .m U UP sD . m P
P .P m
D
.w@
U.
m
\ \' D DD
' o
' o m\ U m@D U a mP
:L .
: .
P : w .P
: .
P : s D P m P .
: L .
: .
. L
appendix
256
D
C D
m\D . m U \ g
m P
o
.
]~ [
PD ~ : \ mP MM DP %
M DP % P .o M %\ : ~
D . :~ \ w mP \
DP m\D . m
'
@ Q 'D @ Q M ~a P . ] [ :@
M
D ' m P \ mP m
D \D mP
@ P
\D mP m
.
.
C :L D.
" " B.L M Q
.L
.
.
: .m
.
.L
" D \D mP m
@ P" .L
257
appendix
D D m
P : @
mP D :
mP \ g
P . %
D .
PD @ D m P
@D P m
D D D Q o p
P \ . P D D : P c w
D % '
P
\ g.
.D :L
: .
:L .
D :L .-
D : .
.L
B .D :L M Qo
:L .
.
D : .
appendix
258
@D -
P D " : \P ms
' ".
D P - " [P :] : \
\ .g
D .g D m mP
P DP ' ] [ :
( .
M D a .
D ".
D
D mP
D M
.
D % m
D
m P : a
m U .
D a a
D
.a
a U
@D
.a
. Qa
PD @ D m P \ U
@
D o [P :L] @ Q \D @ Q
: '.A
: .
D : .
.
: D %a.%
.
:L .
: .
.L
.
259
appendix
@ \ D w a
MD @
D Q D D :
P U D .
: D P D
P D . M
~ ' \
D
D.
D D P P ~ PD
P @
DD .D \ M mP" :~ ]:
[(
" . Z
D
P . P m .m
D
P m :m~
D
P . mP m BP
M\ B mP m\D D . MB
B .mP : M Qo
.
. L
:L .A
.L
: .
: L .
D" " B. M Q
: .
: .m
mP" "m .L
.DP :
:L .D
appendix
260
@D
D BPD . o
.
PD \ m D~ .P mP D
Qa ]DD [ : o P m DD .m P -
P Do a
D m .
D P m P \ gw
D m
% D @ M
D .~ ~
.
PD m P
@ Q D @ Q
@ M MD .
D .
PD D - m P M
%
@ M .
D P @ DP a
@
P @ \ D M
M .
PD D \ % @ A D
MD B P.U
:
:L .
: L .
D" P mP \ g w
D m "
.L
" " : .L .
:L .
.
.
D P.
: DP a
.
261
appendix
w m P
D
D m P ] [P :
P M m PD D M ~
D
@
M .
D D %
' MD
.
PD D ]\ [( :L % @ A
o@PD w P U D
D.%
D ~ %@ mP m
D @D
g DP mP B :
D D % mP
w
\ g D PU
.
P ~ % D %
D P
DD M
D % D%
m P m PD M
( m
:L
D.
.
.
.L
:L .
.L
.m :L
.DP :
.
.L
.M :L
appendix
262
U D ( '\D . m
.
D m
D D (
][
\
D % PD .Q % \g
D
.~ ( :
( D
D !D ! D
] [(:
:
MD !m
P
D@PD D M
D
@ DoD
D @P
D
D : D.
.
D :L .
.L
D :L (.
D" " .L
: .
:L .
.
PD
DD
c'P
D o
p
D
mP c
p Do U BD
D
@
263
appendix
D -P M~ D
M P@
M ( mC Dm
(
@P
~
D
D P D %@
M .P
@( M a
D o
M " PD "wD " "w
D"
".
D" @ m " D\"
"
PD m P M [P :L] P
"MD .
D P
" P
.
"D . m
PD D o ] [P : -\ : D
D DP
m
" "D .L
.D :L
B : M Qo.g
.
@. c
.
.
.
. w
:L .
. w
o :L D D .
. L
.D :
appendix
264
~ D . m D
\ g
'@
D - m
'@ Q
% .
@ M Q \ . M
%D
D U .
% D
\D M
D w
(oP ~ m \' ][ :
P
D "
P" :m
D
D PD . - w
(oP p m % %
\ g\
\ g
.(oP
w
- P@ \ P
@( -\ !Q
D m
D D D . Z@D
.
P U~D P g\ A P .
( DD o D o PD
D P \ PD %
P \ P mP M Z
P mPD % Z
:L D.
: .
:L .
:L .
: L \.
: .%
@ :m a. a
:L .
.L
D :L .
.
265
appendix
D
P ] [( : o
@ Z
D @P !
DP DP g\ ( ' % M Q.Q
D D D m @P D.
.
@D : .
CD .
: @ D :L .
D C .
D :
" @P ... D" M.
266
bibliography
bibliography
267
BIBLIOGRAPHY
1. Al-Rzs Works
(a) Published Works
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
268
35.
36.
37.
38.
bibliography
Tal al-aqq, in Chahrdah risleh ..., ed. S. Sabzawr, Tehran, 1961, 5178
(Persian).
Risla f l-Tanbh #al ba# al-asrr al-mda#a f ba# suwar al-Qur"n al-#am, ed.
B. Drtm, Amman, 2004.
Al-Waiyya, see al-Zarkn, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, 63843.
Ziyrat al-qubr [published as Falsafa-i Ziyrat], ed. A. #$bid, Qom, 1998.
(b) Manuscripts
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
bibliography
269
Bqilln, Muammad Ibn al-ayyib al-. Al-Inf fm yajibu i#tiqduh wa-l yajzu al-jahl
bih, ed. I. \aydar, Beirut, 1986.
Tamhd al-aw"il wa-talkh al-dal"il, ed. R. McCarthy, Beirut, 1957.
Bar, Ab l-\usayn Muammad Ibn #Al al-. Al-Mu#tamad f ul al-fiqh, 2 vols., ed.
M. \amdullh et al., Damascus, 1964.
Busraw, Muaf Ibn Khall Khwja Zde al-. Tahfut al-falsifa, Cairo, 1302 A.H.
Dhahab, Muammad Ibn Amad al-. Trkh al-Islm wa-wafayt al-mashhr wa-l-a#lm,
52 vols., ed. #U. Tadmur, Beirut, 1997.
Frb, Ab Nar Muammad Ibn Muammad al-. $r" ahl al-madna al-fila, ed.
A. Ndir, Beirut, 1968.
Kitb al-Burhn, ed. M. Fakhry, Beirut, 1987.
Galen. On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato, 3 vols., ed. and trans. P. de Lacy, Berlin,
1980.
Ghazl, Muammad Ibn Muammad al-. Iy" #ulm al-dn, 4 vols., Beirut, n.d.
Al-Iqtid f l-i#tiqd, ed. \. Atay et al., Ankara, 1962.
Al-Risla al-Laduniyya, in Majm#at ras"il al-Imm al-Ghazl, Beirut, 1994, 3, 5774.
Mi#yr al-#ilm, ed. S. Duny, Cairo, 1961.
Al-Munqidh min al-all, ed. F. Jabr, Beirut, 1959.
Al-Mustaf min #ilm al-ul, 2 vols., Cairo, 1322 A.H.
Al-Risla al-Qudsiyya, ed. A. Tibawi, in The Islamic Quarterly, 9, 1965, 7994.
Tahfut al-falsifa, ed. S. Duny, Cairo, 1957.
Hind, #Al al-Mattaq #Al" al-Dn al-. Kanz al-#umml, Hyderabad, 1958.
Ibn #Abd al-Hd, Muammad Ibn Amad. Al-#Uqd al-durriyya min manqib Shaykh alIslm Ibn Taymiyya, Beirut, 1974.
Ibn #Abd Rabbih, Amad Ibn Muammad. Al-#Iqd al-fard, ed. A. Amn, 7 vols., Cairo,
1940.
Ibn Ab Uaybi#a, Muwaffaq al-Dn Amad Ibn Qsim. #Uyn al-anb" f abaqt alaibb", 3 vols., Cairo, 1981.
Ibn al-Akfn, Mamd Ibn Ibrhm, Irshd al-qid il asn al-maqid, ed. J. Witkam,
Leiden, 1989.
Ibn #Arafa al-Wargham, Muammad. (Bb al-Imma min kitb) al-Mukhtaar al-shmil,
ed. S. Ghurb, in \awliyyt al-Jmi#a al-Tnisiyya, 9, 1972, 177234.
Ibn al-Athr, #Al Ibn Muammad. Al-Kmil f l-trkh, 13 vols., Beirut, 1966.
Ibn Frak, Muammad Ibn al-\asan. Early Islamic Theological and Juristic Terminology:
Kitb al-udd fi l-ul, ed. M. A. S. Abdel Haleem, London, 1991.
Mujarrad maqlt al-Shaykh Ab l-\asan al-Ash#ar, ed. D. Gimaret, Beirut, 1987.
Ibn al-#Ibr, Gregorios Ab l-Faraj. Trkh mukhtaar al-duwal, ed. A. ln, Beirut,
1958.
Ibn al-#Imd, Shihb al-Dn #Abd al-\ayy Ibn Amad. Shadhart al-dhahab f akhbr man
dhahab, ed. M. al-Arn", Damascus, 1991.
Ibn Kathr, Ism#l Ibn #Umar. Al-Bidya wa-l-nihya, 14 vols., Beirut, 1977.
Ibn Khallikn, Amad Ibn Muammad. Wafayt al-a#yn wa-anb" abn" al-zamn,
6 vols., ed. M. #Abd al-\amd, Cairo, 1948.
Ibn al-Malim, Mamd Ibn Muammad. Al-Mu#tamad f ul al-dn, ed.
M. McDermott and W. Madelung, London, 1991.
Ibn al-Murta, Amad Ibn Yay. Al-Munya wa-l-amal, ed. I. Muammad #Al,
Alexandria, 1985.
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya, Muammad Ibn Ab Bakr. Ijtim# al-juysh al-islmiyya,
Amritsar, 1314 A.H.
Ibn Rushd, Muammad Ibn Amad. Fal al-maql fm bayn al-ikma wa-l-shar#a min
al-ittil, ed. M. #Amra, Beirut, 1981.
Tafsr m ba#d al-ab#a, 3 vols., ed. M. Bouyges, Beirut, 1942.
270
bibliography
bibliography
271
Kiy al-Harrs, #Al Ibn Muammad al-. Ul al-Dn, Ms. 290 Kalm, Dr al-Kutub
al-Miriyya, Cairo.
Ma#arr, Ab l-#Al" al-. Dwn Saq al-Zand, ed. U. al-abb#, Beirut, 1998.
Majr, (Pseudo-) al-. Ghyat al-akm wa-aaqq al-natjatayn bi-l-taqdm, ed. H. Ritter,
Leipzig, 1933.
Picatrix Das Ziel Des Weisen Von Pseudo-Mar, trans. H. Ritter and M. Plessner,
London, 1962.
Maimonides, Moses. The Guide of the Perplexed, 2 vols., trans. S. Pines, Chicago, 1974.
Mward, #Al Ibn Muammad al-. Adab al-duny wa-l-dn, ed. A. Ab Zayna, Cairo,
1979.
A#lm al-nubuwwa, ed. M. al-Baghdd, Beirut, 1987.
Miskawayh, Amad Ibn Muammad. (Min risla ...) f l-ladhdht wa-l-lm, in #A.
Badaw, Dirst wa-nus f l-falsafa wa-l-#ulm #inda l-#Arab, Beirut, 1981, 98104.
Tahdhb al-akhlq, ed. C. Zurayq, Beirut, 1967.
Murta, #Al Ibn al-\usayn al-Sharf al-. Al-Dhakhra f #ilm al-kalm, ed. A. al\usayn, Qom, 1411 A.H.
Mutawall, #Abd al-Ramn Ibn Ma"mn al-. Al-Mughn, ed. M. Bernand, Cairo,
1986.
Plato. The Republic, trans. D. Lee, London, 1987.
Ptolemy. Almagest, trans., G. J. Toomer, New York, 1984.
Qif, Jaml al-Dn Ab l-\asan al-. Ikhbr al-#ulam" bi akhbr al-ukam", Cairo, 1326
A.H.
Ktib elebi, Muaf Ibn #Abd Allh. Kashf al-unn #an asm al-kutub wa-l-funn, ed.
S. Yaltkaya et al., Istanbul, 1941.
Rghib al-Ifahn, al-\usayn Ibn Muammad al-. Al-Dhar#a il makrim al-shar#a, ed.
A. al-#Ajam, Cairo, 1985.
Al-I#tiqdt, ed. Sh. Al-#Ijl, Beirut, 1988.
Rz, Ab Bakr Muammad Ibn Zakariyy al-. [Ras"il falsafiyya], ed. P Kraus, Cairo,
1939.
Al-Shukk #al Jlns, ed. M. Mohaghegh, Tehran, 1413 A.H.
Al-ibb al-rn, ed. #A. Muammad, Cairo, 1978.
afad, Khall Ibn Aybak al-. Al-Wf bi-l-wafayt, 29 vols., ed. S. Dedering, Damascus,
1959.
San", Majdd Ibn $dam al-. \adqat al-aqqa wa-shar#at al-tarqa, ed. M. Razav,
Tehran, 1368 A.H.
The First Book of the \adqat al-\aqqat or the Enclosed Garden of the Truth, trans. M.
Stephenson, Calcutta, 1910.
Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Scepticism, trans. J. Annas and J. Barnes, Cambridge,
2000.
Shahrastn, #Abd al-Karm al-. Al-Milal wa-l-nial, ed. M. al-Kln, 2 vols., Cairo,
1961.
Kitb al-Mura#a, ed. and trans. T. Mayer and W. Madelung, London, 2001.
Nihyat al-iqdm f #ilm al-kalm, ed. A. Guillaume, London, 1934.
Shahrazr, Muammad Ibn Mamd al-. Nuzhat al-arw wa-rawat al-afr, ed. Kh.
Amad, Hyderabad, 1976.
Shrz, Muammad Ibn Ibrhm adr al-Dn al-. Al-\ikma al-muta#liya, 9 vols.,
Beirut, 1990.
Subk, Tj al-Dn #Abd al-Wahhb Ibn #Al al-. abaqt al-Shfi#iyya al-kubr, 10 vols.,
ed. M. al-an et al., Cairo, 1965.
Suhraward, Yay Ibn \abash al-. Haykil al-nr, ed. M. Ab Rayyn, Cairo, 1957.
Taftazn, Mas#d Ibn #Umar Sa#d al-Dn al-. Shar al-Maqid, 5 vols., ed. A. #Umayra,
Beirut and Cairo, 1989.
272
bibliography
Tahnaw, Muammad #Al Ibn #Al al-. Kashshf iilt al-funn, 4 vols., Beirut,
1998.
kprzde, Amad Ibn Muaf. Mift al-sa#da wa-mib al-siyda, 4 vols., ed. K.
Bakr et al., Cairo, 1968.
Tawd, Ab \ayyn #Al Ibn Muammad al-. Al-Hawmil wa-l-shawmil, ed. A.
Amn et al., Cairo, 1951.
Al-Imt# wa-l-mu"nasa, 3 vols., ed. A. Amn et al., Cairo, 1953.
f, Sulaymn Ibn #Abd al-Qaw al-. Dar" al-qawl al-qab bi-l-tasn wa-l-taqb, ed. A.
Shihadeh, Riyadh, 2005.
Al-Ta#yn f shar al-Arba#n, ed. A. #Uthmn, Beirut, 1998.
s, Muammad Ibn Muammad al-. Shar al-Ishrt, printed with Fakhr al-Dn alRzs Shar al-Ishrt.
Talkh al-muaal, ed. A. Nrn, Beirut, 1985.
Warrq, Mamd Ibn al-\asan al-. Dwn al-Warrq, ed. W. Qab, Ajman, 1991.
Yfi#, #Abd Allh Ibn As#ad al-. Mir"t al-jinn wa-#ibrat al-yaqn, 4 vols., Hyderabad,
1338 A.H.
Zamakhshar, Mamd Ibn #Umar al-. Al-Minhj f ul al-dn, ed. S. Schmidtke,
Stuttgart, 1997.
3. Modern Works
Ahlwardt, Wilhelm. Die HandschriftenVerzeichnisse der Kniglichen Bibliothek
zu Berlin, XVI, in Verzeichniss der Arabischen Handschriften, V, Berlin, 1893.
Anawati, Georges C. Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz; Elments de biographie, in Melanges H.
Masse, Tehran, 1963, 110.
Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz; tamhd li-dirsat aytih wa-mu"allaftih, in Melanges h \usain,
ed. #A. Badaw, Cairo, 1962, 193234.
Barnes, Jonathan. Some Ways of Scepticism, in Epistemology, ed. S. Everson,
Cambridge, 1990, 20424.
Bell, Joseph N. Love Theory in Later \anbalite Islam, Albany, 1979.
Black, Deborah L. Practical Wisdom, Moral Virtue, and Theoretical Knowledge:
The Problem of the Autonomy of the Practical Realm in Arabic Philosophy, in
Les philosophies morales et politiques au Moyen ge, ed. B. Bazn et al., Ottawa, 1995,
45164.
Brink, David O. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge, 1989.
Brockelmann, Carl. Geschichte der arabischen Litteratur, 5 vols., Leiden, 19371949.
Budr, Salmn al-. Naariyyat Ibn Sn f l-fi#l, in Dirst, 15, 1988, 6273.
Calder, Norman. The Barhima: Literary Construct and Historical Reality, in
Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, 57(1), 1994, 4051.
Ceylan, Yasin. Theology and Tafsir in the Major Works of Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, Kuala
Lampur, 1996.
Cook, Michael. Commanding Right and Forbidding Wrong in Islamic Thought, Cambridge,
2001.
Davidson, Herbert A. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect, Oxford, 1992.
De Beaurecueil, P. S. L. Al-Makht al-#Arabiyya f Afghnistn, in Majallat Ma#had alMakht al-#Arabiyya, 2(1), 1956, 333.
Encyclopedia of Ethics, 2 vols., Chicago and London, 1992. [EE].
Encyclopaedia of Islam (The), New Edition, 12 vols., Leiden, 19602004. [EI2].
Encyclopdia Iranica, 13 vols. to date, London, 1982.
Ess, Josef van. Die Erkenntnislehre des #Audaddin al-^c, Wiesbaden, 1966.
The Logical Structure of Islamic Theology, in Logic in Classical Islamic Culture;
Giorgio Levi Della Vida Conferences, ed. G. Grunebaum, Los Angeles, 1967, 2150.
bibliography
273
274
bibliography
in International Congress for the Study of the Quran, Canberra, 1980, 93111.
Kagan, Shelly. Normative Ethics, Boulder, 1998.
Kamali, Mohammad Hashim. Principles of Islamic Jurisprudence, Cambridge, 1997.
Kholeif, Fathallah. A Study on Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz and His Controversies in Transoxiana,
Beirut, 1966.
Lagarde, Michel. Index du Grand Commentaire de Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, Leiden, 1996.
Lambton, Ann K. S. State and Government in Medieval Islam, Oxford, 1991.
Leaman, Oliver. Abd [sic.] al-Jabbar and the Concept of Uselessness, Journal of
the History of Ideas, 41(1), 12931.
Macdonald, Duncan B. The Development of the Idea of Spirit in Islam, Muslim
World, 22, 1932, 2542; 15368.
Madelung, Wilferd. The Late Mu#tazila and Determinism: The Philosophers
Trap, in Yd-Nma: In Memoria di Alessandro Bausani, ed. S. Amoretti, Rome,
1991, vol.1, 24557.
Mar#ash, Mamd. Fihrist nuskheh-ye kha Kitbkhane #Umm \azrat $yat Allh al#Um Mar#ash Najaf, Qom, 1975.
Marmura, Michael E. Avicennas Psychological Proof of Prophecy, in Journal of Near
Eastern Studies, 1963, 22(1), 4656.
Avicennas Theory of Prophecy in the Light of Ash#arite Theology, in The Seed of
Wisdom, ed. W. McCullough, Toronto, 1964, 159178.
Al-Ghazl on Ethical Premises, in The Philosophical Forum, 1.iii (New Series),
1969, 393403.
Fakhr al-Dn al-Rzs Critique of an Avicennan Tanbh, in Historia Philosophiae
Medii Aevi II, ed. B. Mojsisch et al., Amsterdam, 1991, 627637.
The Islamic Philosophers Conception of Islam, in Islams Understanding of Itself;
Eighth Giorgio Levi Della Vida Biennial Conference, ed. R. Hovinnisian, California,
1981, 87102.
A Medieval Islamic Argument for the Intrinsic Value of the Moral Act, in Corolla
Torontonensis; Studies in Honour of Ronald Morton Smith, ed. Emmet Robbins et al.,
Toronto, 1994, 11331.
McChesney, Robert. Catalogue of Arabic Manuscripts (Yahuda Section) in the Garret Collection,
Princeton, 1977.
McDermott, Martin J. Abul-\usayn al-Bar on Gods Volition, in Culture and
Memory in Medieval Islam: Essays in Honour of Wilferd Madelung, ed. F. Daftary et al.,
London, 2003.
Michot, Jean R. Ibn Sn. Lettre au Vizir Ab Sa#d, Beirut, 2000.
La Destine de lhomme selon Avicenne: le retour Dieu (ma#d) et limagination, Louvain,
1986.
A Mamlk Theologians Commentary on Avicennas Risla Aawiyya, being a
translation of part of Dar" al-Ta#ru of Ibn Taymiyya, with introduction, annotation
and appendices, Part I, Journal of Islamic Studies, 14(2), 2003, 149203.
Vanits intellectuelles... Limpasse des rationalismes selon le rejet de la contradiction dIbn Taymiyya, in Oriente Moderno, 19, 2000, 597617.
Mohaghegh, Mahdi. Flsf-i-Rayy Mohammad Ibn-i-Zakary-i Rz, Tehran, 1970.
Nasr, Seyyed H. Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, in A History of Muslim Philosophy, ed. M. Sharif,
2 vols., Wiesbaden, 1963, 1, 64256.
Ormsby, Eric L. Theodicy in Islamic Thought; The Dispute over al-Ghazalis Best of All
Possible Worlds, Princeton, 1984.
Ragep, F. Jamil. Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy: an Aspect of Islamic Influence
on Science, in Osiris, 2001, 16, 4971.
Rahman, Fazlur. Avicennas Psychology. An English Translation of Kitb Al-Najt, Book II,
Chapter VI, Oxford, 1952.
bibliography
275
276
bibliography
index of names
277
INDEX OF NAMES
#Abd al-Jabbr 21 n. 34, 23, 24 n. 46,
25, 27, 28, 33, 4749, 75 n. 113, 77
n. 123, 93 n. 172
#Abduh, Muammad 44
Abraham 137 n. 128
Ab l-Barakt al-Baghdd 8, 117 n. 36,
118, 199
Ab l-Hayam 117 n. 36
Ab Lahab 103
Adam 45 n. 2
Akhbrs 117 n. 36
#Al Ibn Ab lib 135
Aristotle 19 n. 25, 118, 125, 198
Al-Aamm, Ab Bakr 178
Al-Ash#ar, Ab l-\asan 18, 19, 20, 83
Ash#ars; Ash#arism 24, 6, 7, 8,
1315, 1719, 21, 35 n. 94, 3941,
4347, 4957, 61, 64, 65, 66, 68,
73, 75, 7879, 8285, 87, 88, 91,
94, 96, 97, 101, 104107, 109, 110,
117 n. 36, 129132, 141, 142, 150
Al-Bhil, Ab l-\asan 4 n. 6
Al-Bqilln 7, 15, 39, 40, 66, 104, 107,
114
Al-Bar, Ab l-\usayn 2, 16, 17, 25,
26, 35, 36, 9194, 178, 179
Barhima 133
Carneades 198
Christians 117 n. 36
Al-Dabs, Ab Zayd 117 n. 36
Al-Dawwn 164 n. 34
Determinists 38, 96
4irr Ibn #Amr 38
4iy" al-Dn al-Rz 4
Dualists 185
Euclid
191
114, 117
Ibn al-Akfn 2
Ibn Frak 15, 34, 50, 51, 53
Ibn al-Malim 16, 2528, 49, 93
Ibn al-Murta 25 n. 50
Ibn al-Nu#mn, Muammad 117 n. 36
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya 209 n. 13
Ibn Rushd 19 n. 25
Ibn Sn 2 n. 1, 8, 9, 11, 19, 21, 27,
42, 58, 61, 8890, 97 n. 188, 101,
110, 112, 117 n. 36, 118, 120, 122,
124127, 130132, 137141, 143 n.
146, 148, 151, 159, 161164, 166, 168,
179, 180
Ibn Taymiyya 3637 n. 99, 109, 199,
201, 209 n. 13
Ikhwn al-af" 130, 142
Al-Isfar"n, Ab Isq 4 n. 6, 7, 15,
16, 51, 104, 105
Ism#ls 138, 139
Israelites 135 n. 119
Al-Ji 134, 136, 138, 141, 178179,
197
Jahm Ibn afwn 38
Jahms 36 n. 99
278
index of names
Philoponos, John
Plato 118, 159
Ptolemy 197
197
Qadars 37 n. 99
Quraysh 181
Qub al-Dn al-Shrz
197 n. 146
178
index of subjects
279
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
13, 14 n. 3, 3941
280
index of subjects