Monism and Monotheism in Al-Ghazali's Mişkat - Treiger
Monism and Monotheism in Al-Ghazali's Mişkat - Treiger
Mishkdt al-anwdr
Alexander Treiger
YALE UNIVERSITY
For the purposes of the present study, the term 'monism' refers to the theory, put
forward by al-Ghazall in a number of contexts, that God is the only existent in
existence and the world, considered in itself, is 'sheer non-existence' Cadam mahd);
while 'monotheism' refers to the view that God is the one of the totality of existents
which is the source of existence for the rest of existents. The fundamental difference
between the two views lies in their respective assessments of God's granting
existence to what is other than He: the monistic paradigm views the granting of
existence as essentially virtual so that in the last analysis God alone exists, whereas
the monotheistic paradigm sees the granting of existence as real.^
I am not aware of any study that puts these passages together. Yet they are so closely
related that they cannot be read in isolation from one another:
What I wish to suggest at this point is that the two passages refiect two distinct
themes or perspectives present in the Mishkdt and in al-Ghazali's theology in
general. The first perspective can be described as monistic; the second, as
monotheistic. Indeed, according to the first passage, God is the only true existent, the
other existents possessing only borrowed and metaphorical existence - hence
monism. According to the second passage, by contrast, God is the Lord and Creator
(/ turn my face as a true believer to Him who created the heavens and the earth) and
while the divinity of the intermediary 'lords' is rejected their existence is never
denied - hence monotheism.
Let us start with Passage A and with the monistic perspective. As stated above, the
term monism refers to the view - put forward by al-Ghazali in a number of contexts
in several works - that 'There is nothing in existence save God' {laysa fl'l-wujud
y^ and that the world is 'sheer non-existence' {"adam mahd).^^
The theme of God as the only true existent is central to al-Ghazall's metaphysics. It
occurs, most famously, as the highest stage of professing God's oneness, tawhld.^'^ In
the Mishkdt itself, as we have seen toward the end of Passage A, al-Ghazall draws a
distinction between two types of tawhld, characteristic of the commoners and the
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazall's Mishkat al-anwdr 5
elect respectively. The commoners believe in the plain meaning of the shahdda,
'There is no god but God'. The elect, by contrast, have a more esoteric version,
which reads: 'There is no god but He'. An even more esoteric version, 'There is no
he but He' {Id huwa Hid huwa) is mentioned earlier in the same passage without
attribution. The implication is that this is the tawhld of the elect among the elect,
khawdss al-khawdss, a group mentioned elsewhere in the Mishkdt.'^
In several of his works al-Ghazali discusses tawhld and divides it into a number of
levels or stages {mardtib). The best known - fourfold - classification is found in
Book 35 ofthe Ihyd' {Kitdb al-Tawhld wa'l-tawakkul), in the corresponding sections
of Kitdb al-Arba'^in and the Persian Klmiyd-ye sa'^ddat, and in Kitdb al-Imld' fi
ishkdldt al-Ihyd" - a work supplementary to the Ihya" and written to rebut criticisms
directed at the latter. A slightly different classification is presented in one of al-
Ghazali's Persian letters. There, tawhld is divided into six levels. In the following
discussion I shall take the fourfold classification of the Ihyd^ as a basis, providing
references to other classifications in endnotes where appropriate.
In Book 35 of the Ihyd^ al-Ghazali divides tawhld into four levels and compares
them, respectively, to a nut's husk of the husk, husk, kernel and kernel of the kernel,
progressing from the most outward dimension to the innermost.
see himself. In this stage one sees the universe (al-kuU) not insofar as it is
many but insofar as it is one (min haythu innahu wahid)}^ This contemplation
is sometimes lasting but more often comes as a flash of lightning.^'
It is important to note that in referring to the fourth level of tawhld al-Ghazall is not
speaking of a purely subjective state of the mystic, who, being totally devoted to and
focused on God, sees nothing else - not even himself - in existence; whose vision,
however, does not correspond to the actual state of affairs, where both God and
creation exist. Such purely subjectivistic interpretation ignores the fact that the
fourth level of tawhld has, for al-Ghazall, an important cognitive content, which he
seeks to analyse and explain in rational terms or through images, as we shall see
below.^° It is with this cognitive content and the ontology revealed therein, not
merely with the psychological state that leads to its realisation, that he is primarily
concerned. This is why he is not content with the SufT designation of this state as
'obliteration' (fana^), which overemphasises the subjective and experiential side,
and insists on calling it tawhld, emphasising its ontological aspect.
It is for this reason, too, that al-Ghazali is careful to reject alternative ontological
interpretations of this state: he wants to ensure that the ontology it reveals is
adequately interpreted and understood. This is the purpose of the following
comment, made by al-Ghazall in the Persian letter mentioned above, in which he
criticises the 'ecstatic' Suffs al-Hallaj (d. 309/922) and Abu Yazld al-BistamI (d.
261/874 or 264/877-8) who, in his view, failed adequately to interpret their
experience:
The notion that it is not only in a mystic's subjective experience but also in actuality
that (in the last analysis) there is nothing in existence save God is a striking one, and
al-Ghazall is very much aware that it will raise some eyebrows. He therefore
attempts to forestall criticism by offering a variety of partial but complementary
explanations.^" The most revealing of these is to be found in the first part of the
Mishkat and in the Persian letter mentioned above. These texts are cited below side
by side: the former in paraphrase, the latter in translation.
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazall's Mishkat al-anwar
Here, in the Mishkat and the Persian letter, al-Ghazall provides theoretical
justification for his radical claim that 'There is nothing in existence save God': the
'borrowed' and hence 'metaphorical' nature of the existence of created things.^'
What is the origin of this idea? In order to answer this question let us notice that
while consonant with important developments within the Sufi tradition''^ al-Ghazall's
monistic ontology is critical of some aspects of that tradition (the ecstatic
pronouncements of al-Hallaj and al-BistamI as well as Sufi terminology) and on the
other hand can be shown to stand on a firm philosophical foundation. Specifically, it
bears a striking structural resemblance to, and integrates important elements of,
Avicenna's metaphysics, especially Avicenna's quiddity/existence distinction and
the proof for the existence of God.''
It can be seen that in the passages cited above al-Ghazall's discussion follows the
structure and conceptual framework of Avicenna's argument quite closely, with only
occasional modifications and 're-naming' of some of the concepts:
1. Al-Ghazall's 'light' (in the Mishkat passage) is another term for existence, as
al-Ghazall himself makes clear in Mishkat, Part 1, §40.''°
2. The hierarchy of lights, emanating light upon one another, corresponds to
Avicenna's chain of efficient causes, bestowing existence upon one another.
The First Source of these lights corresponds to Avicenna's first efficient cause.
3. The 'borrowed' nature of existence corresponds to the fact that in Avicenna's
system existence is bestowed upon a quiddity by an external efficient cause
(and ultimately by the First Cause).
4. The perpetual 'perishing' of all existents corresponds to their 'possible' nature
{imkdn) in Avicenna's system. This explains why, according to al-Ghazall,
their perishing is 'from eternity to eternity' {azalan wa-abadan): although, in
contradistinction to Avicenna, al-Ghazali sees the world as created in time, the
world's possible nature, that is, its being capable of existence or non-existence,
is nevertheless eternal.*'
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazali's Mishkat al-anwar 9
Al-Ghazall's use of the concept of 'face' in the Mishkdt and of the Qur'anic phrase
everything is perishing save His Face undoubtedly goes back to this and similar
Avicennian passages. It is also worth noting that when al-Ghazall speaks of the
fourth degree of tawhld he usually calls God 'the One, the Real' {al-wdhid al-
haqq),*^ providing a direct link to this passage by Avicenna, in which God's name
'the Real' is analysed. Moreover, in his commentary on the Divine Names, al-
Maqsad al-asnd fl sharh ma'^dnl asmd^ Alldh al-husnd - a work written after the
Ihyd'' but prior to the Mishkdt^ - al-Ghazali explains that the name al-haqq refers to
the essence {dhdt) of God insofar as it is necessary of existence {wdjibat al-wujud),
again alluding to Avicenna. All this leaves al-Ghazall's debt to Avicenna beyond
reasonable doubt.
Let us now turn to Passage B and the monotheistic perspective. Hermann Landolt in
his important study on the Mishkdt, 'Ghazall and Religionswissenschaft', published
in 1991, pointed out that this passage is closely related to the third part - the so-
called 'Veil Section' - of the Mishkdt."*^ This section is devoted to an interpretation
of the Veils Hadith: 'God has 70 [in some versions: 70,000] veils of light and
darkness; were He to lift them, the glories of His Face would burn up everyone
whose sight perceived Him'. Following this hadith, al-Ghazall presents a
classification of human beings into four categories: (1) those veiled from God by
pure darkness, (2) those veiled by darkness mixed with light, (3) those veiled by pure
light, and finally (4) the attainers (al-wdsilUn). It is essential for our purposes to deal
with the last two categories in detail.
The third category is divided into three groups: first, those (group 3.1) who know the
true meaning of the divine attributes (such as speech, will, power and knowledge)
and realise that there is no connection between the application of these terms to God
and to other existents, including humans. Hence they avoid naming God by these
attributes and refer to Him merely through the relation {iddfa) He has to created
beings, as did Moses in his response to Pharaoh's question 'What is the Lord of the
worlds?' (Q. 26:23). This group believes that the Lord transcends the meanings of
the attributes and is the mover and caretaker of the heavens {muharrik al-samdwdt
wa-mudabbiruhd).^^
The second group (3.2) realises that there is plurality in the heavens and that each
sphere is moved by a separate angel, the angels being multiple and analogous to stars
{nisbatuhum ild [read /T?] al-anwdr al-ildhiyya nisbat al-kawdkib)?^ Hence they
conclude that the Lord is the mover of the outermost celestial body encompassing all
the spheres {al-jirm al-aqsd al-muntawl ''ald'l-afldk kullihd), who is untouched by
plurality.
The third group (3.3) realises that the mover of the outermost celestial body causes
the motion of the heavens directly {bi-tariq al-mubdshara). Since it is not fitting for
the Lord to be the direct cause of motion, the mover of the outermost celestial body
cannot be the Lord but an angel, standing at the Lord's service and analogous to the
moon {nisbatuhu ild [read /T?] al-anwdr al-ildhiyya al-mahda nisbat al-qamar)^^
They believe that the Lord is the Being that is obeyed by this mover {al-mutd" min
jihat hddhd'l-muharrikf^ and moves the universe not directly but by way of
command {bi-tarlq al-amr)^'^
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazali's Mishkat al-anwar 11
So far the threefold division of the third category. Finally, the fourth category (group
4), the attainers, are those who realise that even this obeyed one {al-mutd'^) has a
quality that is at odds with pure singularity, 'on account of a secret that cannot be
disclosed in this book',^^ and that the obeyed one is analogous to the sun among
[sensible] lights {nisbat hddhd'l-mutd" nisbat al-shams fl'l-anwdr)?^ This is why
they turn their faces away from the movers of the heavens, the mover of the
outermost celestial body, and the obeyed one, by whose command it is moved,
toward Him who created {fatara) them all.
As noted by Landolt, both Passage B and the Veil Section are parallel to, and based
on, Abraham's gradual ascent to belief in God in Q. 6:76-9. According to the
Qur'anic passage, Abraham saw a star and declared, 'This is my Lord {hddhd rabbi)'
(Q. 6:76), yet when the star disappeared beneath the horizon, Abraham said, '/ do
not like those that set {al-dfdln)' (Q. 6:76). Then the moon rose and Abraham
declared again, 'This is my Lord' (Q. 6:77); but the moon set, too. Next, the sun
appeared and Abraham exclaimed, 'This is my Lord, [for] this is greater' (Q. 6:78).
Finally, after the sun disappeared as well, Abraham renounced all forms of idolatry
and proclaimed, '/ turn my face as a true believer to Him who created the heavens
and the earth' (Q. 6:79).
In the case of Passage B the Qur'anic substratum is evident, since this passage
alludes to Abraham's ascent to belief in God by quoting the relevant ayas. In the
case of the Veil Section, too, the threefold division of those veiled by pure light is
based on the Qur'anic account of Abraham's ascent. The three groups 3.1, 3.2 and
3.3 are differentiated according to which among the Lord's angels they mistakenly
believe to be the Lord: whether the movers of the heavens, analogous to the stars
(group 3.1), or the mover of the outermost celestial body, analogous to the moon
(group 3.2), or the obeyed one, analogous to the sun (group 3.3). Finally, the fourth
category, the attainers, go beyond all these and turn their faces toward Him who
created them all, as Abraham did.
What makes the connection between Passage B and the Veil Section even closer is
that in Passage B al-Ghazall is not speaking of physical lights (the stars, the moon
and the sun), but of a spiritual and angelic hierarchy that runs parallel to the physical
one. The 'star', the 'moon' and the 'sun' that the 'traveller' encounters on his way
are not the physical star, moon and sun but the spiritual substances (angels)
corresponding to these. The 'traveller', in fact, encounters in succession the very
same three angels that the three groups 3.1, 3.2 and 3.3 mistakenly view as the Lord.
Why does the traveller turn away from the 'sun' - i.e. from the 'sun-angel' (=the
obeyed one of the third part of the Mishkdt)! According to Landolt, he does so
because the 'sun[-angel]' is 'greater and higher than the moon[-angel]' and, being
'related to something less perfect' than itself, is itself imperfect.^* This however is
12 Journal of Qur'anic Studies
not precisely what al-Ghazall says. Al-Ghazall's text reads (to quote Passage B
It is clear that the imperfection of the sun-angel derives not from the fact that it is
greater and higher than the moon-angel, as Landolt interprets it, but from the fact
that this angel has a physical image {mithdl) - the sun - with which it has analogous
correspondence {mundsaba). This, in my view, helps solve one of the puzzles of the
Veil Section, namely why al-Ghazali refrains from identifying the obeyed one with
the Lord: the obeyed one falls short of the ultimate perfection precisely because it
still has an image in the sensible world - the sun. This may be the meaning of al-
Ghazali's statement quoted earlier that 'the obeyed one has a quality that is at odds
with pure singularity and utmost perfection, on account of a secret that cannot be
disclosed in this book'.*°
As al-Ghazali further explains, the terms 'heavens' and 'earth' stand for the two
worlds, the spiritual/intelligible 'world of concealment and the [divine] kingdom'
{'^dlam al-ghayb wa'l-malakut) and the bodily/sensible 'world of possession and
manifestation' {'dlam al-mulk wa'l-shahdda).^^ Thus, al-Ghazali's exegesis of
Q. 6:79 implies that although there is analogous correspondence {mundsaba)
between the worlds - the sensible world consisting of images {amthila) of the
intelligible one - He who created these worlds {alladhifatara'l-samdwdti wa'l-ard)
has no image and transcends {mutanazzih) any analogous correspondence.
worlds, to which he resorts in this passage.^ In the second part of the Mishkdt the
following explanation is provided:*^
On the epistemological level, the analogous correspondence between the two worlds
is highly significant, for if it did not exist one would be unable to ascend to the world
of [divine] kingdom at all.*^ This is why al-Ghazali regards this analogous
correspondence as a sign of divine mercy. On the ontological level, the analogous
correspondence between the two worlds results from the fact that the world of
manifestation is caused by the world of kingdom and, as al-Ghazali says, 'the caused
is always parallel to {muwdzdt) the cause and imitates {muhdkdt) it in some way, be
it proximate or remote'.*' In other words, the image corresponds to that whose image
it is precisely because it is caused by it and hence receives its imprint.
From this passage we learn that al-Ghazali's 'image' (mithdl) does not resemble that
whose image it is in any direct sense but through sharing the same 'spiritual
meaning' or, in modern terms, an abstract quality.™ Furthermore, and this is
important, this quality is relational and refers to the role the two analogues play in
their respective systems. The only sense in which the sultan, for instance, is similar
to the sun is that they share an abstract quality, 'being above all', and perform the
same function in, and relate in the same way to other members of, their respective
systems: the sultan to the minister and the subjects and the sun to the moon and the
sublunar world. Al-Ghazali's analogous correspondence {mundsaba) is therefore
systemic: the two systems - in this case, the system of a country's administration and
the system of celestial luminaries - correspond to each other as a whole.
This holds true also for cosmological symbolism: the similarity of the obeyed one to
the sun is not direct. Rather, they share the same abstract quality, 'being above all'
again, and the same function, emanating lights upon the angel or the luminary
immediately beneath them. Here too the analogous correspondence is systemic: the
two systems - that of spiritual lights and that of celestial luminaries - correspond to
each other as a whole.
It is in this sense that God is said to have no image and transcend any analogous
correspondence: no abstract quality pertaining to created beings - not even the
obeyed one's quality of 'being above all' - can be legitimately predicated of God,
whose function in the universe, as its Creator, has no counterpart within the created
universe itself.
I hope to have shown that both the monistic and the monotheistic perspective are
present in al-Ghazali's Mishkdt al-anwdr. It might be useful at this point to discuss
how the two are related. I therefore suggest looking at the two passages analysed in
the course of this study from the point of view of Avicenna's quiddity/existence
distinction, already invoked in the first section of this study. The terms huwiyya and
mdhiyya, 'encoded', as we have noticed above, in Passages A and B respectively,
provide a formal justification for this approach.
Once we do so, it becomes clear that Passage A, which I have called monistic,
analyses the relation between God and the world from the perspective of existence.
From this perspective, contingent quiddities, considered in themselves, are sheer
non-existence {"adam mahd). They borrow existence from God. God, by contrast, is
pure existence, which lends itself out to non-existent quiddities to render them
'quasi-existent'. In the last analysis, however, only God exists in the real sense, only
He has a 'he-ness' (or 'existence', huwiyya) and only He can be referred to {Id
ishdra illd ilayhi). The tawhld of the elect among the elect, 'There is no he but He'
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazali's Mishkat al-anwar 15
{Id huwa illd huwa), means simply that, there being nothing but God, any reference
is a reference to Him.''
It is also possible to look at the two passages from the point of view of the standard
opposition between, and complementarity of, tashblh and tanzlh, or God's
immanence and transcendence. Seen from this perspective. Passage A represents
tashblh carried to its logical conclusion: to the degree that a contingent existent
exists it is identical with God (or God's Face) and, conversely, to the degree that it is
not identical with God it does not exist (is 'sheer non-existence'). Passage B, by
contrast, represents the tanzlh perspective, highlighting the absolute incomparability
between God and creatures.
Passages A and B can also be regarded as representing two different ways to reach
the stage of facing God. The first way is conceptual; it consists in rejecting the very
concept of contingent quiddity as being ultimately unreal and non-existent. This
leaves one immediately facing God alone as the only real existent. The second way
is experiential; it leads to the same conclusion through the (often gradual) leaving
behind of all the contingent existents as being not-God and hence as ultimately
irrelevant.'^ One faces God only at the very end of this process, after all the veils
have been removed and all contingent existents, in the world of manifestation and
the world of [divine] kingdom alike, have been rejected.
The following passage at the very end of the Veil Section describes the attainment of
this stage by followers of the second way:'"*
It is clear that the experiential way, as practiced by the Sufis, often lacks the
conceptual clarity required to explain what it is that one has experienced. Al-Ghazali
reminds us of this by referring back to the first part of the Mishkdt, where he
criticised the ecstatic utterances of al-Hallaj and al-Bistami, which in his view refiect
erroneous interpretations of this experience as 'union' and 'indwelling' (see above).
This is why al-Ghazali's advice to those who have attained this experience - but are
not qualified to interpret it - is to refrain from mentioning more than the poet's
line:''
There was what there was, which I do not recall // so think [of me]
well and do not ask for a [detailed] account (khabar).
On the other hand, neither is the conceptual way, the way of theoretical knowledge
alone, sufficient in itself, for knowledge C^ilm) is inferior to experiential realisation.
or 'tasting' (dhawq)^ It is only through a thorough philosophical training and
experience (in this order) that one can hope to face God as al-Hallaj and al-Bistami
did, at the same time avoiding their errors in interpreting this experience.
It is this union between conceptual rigor and an experiential path, and more broadly
between philosophy and Sufism (in this order) that constituted al-Ghazali's
theological agenda. He did not, as is often believed, renounce philosophy to adopt a
kind of un- or even anti-philosophical mystical worldview. To the contrary, he
criticised precisely those tenets of Sufism (the ecstatic pronouncements of al-Hallaj
and al-Bistami) that he considered philosophically untenable, while his Sufism
remained philosophical through and through.'^ His use of Avicenna's ideas, as we
have seen especially in the first part of this study, represents an important milestone
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazali's Mishkat al-anwdr 17
Lest the idea of a 'philosophical Sufism' sound like an oxymoron, let us take a brief
look at a passage from Abu Rayhan al-BTrunl's (d. after 442/1050) famous book on
India. Al-BlrunT - more than half a century before al-Ghazall's time - regards the
Sufi tradition as having close affinity with philosophy, so much so that he derives
the term 'Sufi' from the Greek sophia, 'wisdom'.^" Even more significantly, the
passage in which this etymology occurs deals with monistic doctrines of the Ancient
Greeks, in comparison to those of the Indians and the Sufis. It deserves to be quoted
in full:^'
Whether or not there is a grain of truth in al-Birunl's etymology and his account of
the history of Sufism, it is evident that the Sufism he had in mind was of a
philosophical bent, with a pronounced monistic tendency. It is this trend of Sufism
that al-Ghazall followed, reinforcing it further by integrating in his monistic
ontology important elements of Avicenna's metaphysics.
18 Journal of Qur' anic Studies
NOTES
1 An earlier version of this paper was presented at the conference 'The Qur'an: Text,
Interpretation and Translation', School of Oriental and African Studies, London, 10-12
November 2005.1 wish to thank the organisers ofthe conference for inviting me to SOAS and
the participants for important feedback. An earlier version of the first part of this paper was
also presented at the annual meeting ofthe American Oriental Society in Seattle, 17-20 March
2006.1 owe a similar debt of gratitude to the organisers and participants of the AOS meeting.
Finally, my thanks go to the two reviewers at the JQS for their helpful suggestions and
encouragement.
References to the Mishkat, including paragraph numbers, follow the Arabic text printed in al-
Ghazall, The Niche of Lights, tr. D. Buchman (Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press,
1998). Other editions of the Mishkat were consulted as well: (1) ed. Ahmad 'Izzat and Faraj
Allah Zaki al-Kurdi (Cairo: Matba'at al-Sidq, 1322/1904-5); (2) ed. Abu'l-'Ala' 'Aflfl
(Cairo: al-Dar al-Qawmiyya li'1-Tiba'a wa'1-Nashr, 1964); (3) ed. al-Sayrawan (Beirut: 'Alam
al-Kutub, 1407/1986). Al-Sayrawan's edition is based on one of the earliest known
manuscripts of the Mishkdt, Beirut MS AUB 325, copied in 541/1147. Other works by al-
Ghazall are abbreviated as follows: Arba'in = Kitdb al-arba'Tn fi usul al-din, ed. 'A.°A.
'UrwanI and M.B. al-Shaqafa (Damascus: Dar al-Qalam, 1424/2003); Fadd'ih = Fadd'ih al-
bdtiniyya, ed. "A. Badawl (Cairo: al-Dar al-Qawmiyya li'l-Tiba'a wa'l-Nashr,1383/1964);
Faysal = Faysal al-tafriqa bayn al-Isldm wa'l-zandaqa, ed. M. Biju (Damascus: n.p.,
1993/1413); Ihyd' = Ihyd' 'ulum al-din (5 vols, Cairo: al-Maktaba al-Tawfiqiyya, n.d.); lmld'
= al-Imla' fi ishkdldt al-Ihyd^, appended to the edition of the Ihyd', vol. 5, pp. 282-326;
Iqtisdd = al-Iqtisddfi'l-i'tiqdd, ed. LA. ^ubuk9U and H. Atay (Ankara: Nur Matbaasi,1962);
Jawdhir = Jawdhir al-Qur'dn (Beirut: Dar al-Afaq al-Jadlda, 1397/1977); Klmiyd = Kimiyd-
ye sa'ddat, ed. Hoseyn Khadiv Jam (2 vols, Tehran: Sherkat-e Entesharat-e 'Elml va
Farhangi, 1383Sh/2004); Makdtib = Makdtlb-e fdrsi-ye Chazzdli be-ndm-e Fadd'il al-andm
min rasd'il hujjat al-Isldm, ed. 'Abbas Eqbal (Tehran: Ketabforushl-ye Ebn-e Sina,
1333Sh/1954); Maqdsid = Maqdsid al-faldsifa, ed. M.S. al-KurdI (Cairo: al-Matba'a al-
Mahmudiyya al-Tijariyya bi'1-Azhar, 1355/1936); Maqsad = al-Maqsad al-asnd ft sharh
ma'^dniasmd' Alldh al-husnd, ed. F.A. Shehadi (Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq, 1971); Munqidh = al-
Munqidh min al-daldl, ed. J. Sallba and K. 'Ayyad (Beirut: Dar al-Andalus, 1387/1967) (the
paragraph numbers follow R.J. McCarthy's translation of the text in his Freedom and
Fulfillment: An Annotated Translation of al-Ghazdli's al-Munqidh min al-daldl and Other
Relevant Works of al-Ghazali (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1980)); Tahdfut = Tahafut al-
falasifa, ed. M. Bouyges (Beirut: Imprimerie catholique, 1927). References to chapters and
subdivisions of each work are given where possible. All translations in this study are my own.
2 The questions of creation in time versus perpetual creation and creation ex nihilo versus
creation from preexistent matter need not concern us here. What is important for our purposes
is that the monotheistic paradigm acknowledges creation (in any sense of the term) as a real
and fundamental fact.
3 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 1, §§52-4, p. 20, lines 3-20.
4 The textual corrections are based on another edition of the Mishkat, ed. al-Sayrawan, p.
144; cf. H. Landolt, 'Ghazall and Religionswissenschaft: Some Notes on the Mishkdt al-
Anwdr', Etudes Asiatiques 45:1 (1991), pp. 19-72, at p. 61.
5 Adding muwajjih as suggested by Landolt, 'GhazalT and Religionswissenschaft', p. 61, n.
166 (where muwajjihun is almost certainly a mistake, and should probably read muwajjihun).
6 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 2, §§11-15, p. 27, line 15 to p. 28, line 19.
7 The perfect often has the performative meaning of '[a]n act which is just completed at the
moment, and by the very act, of speaking' - W. Wright, A Grammar ofthe Arabic Language
(2 vols, Cambridge: University Press, 1896-8 and reprints), vol. 2, p. lB, §ld.
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazall's Mishkdt al-anwdr 19
8 This is a provisional translation of the complex term lianif on which see most recently F.
de Blois, 'Nasrdni {Nazoraios) and hanif {ethnikos): Studies on the Religious Vocabulary of
Christianity and of Islam', Bulletin of the Society of Oriental and African Studies 65:1 (2002),
pp. 1-30, at pp. 16ff., with relevant bibliography.
9 This term will be clarified in what follows.
10 On this term, see most recently P. Adamson, 'Before Essence and Existence: al-Kindl's
Conception of Being', Journal ofthe History of Philosophy 40 (2002), pp. 297-312, passim,
esp. pp. 299-300 for references to earlier literature.
11 For a comparable treatment of the dialogue between Moses and Pharaoh see the passage
from the Epistles ofthe Brethren of Purity, Epistle no. 4.1 [42], referred to by Landolt,
'Ghazall and Religionswissenschaft', p. 29.
12 This formula occurs in al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 36, baydn 8, vol. 4, p. 444, line 28; Maqsad,
p. 59, line 1; Mishkdt, part 1, §42, p. 16 (as noted by Landolt, 'Ghazall and
Religionswissenschaft', p. 60, this is the only section in the entire work entitled haqiqat al-
haqd'iq), and in one of al-Ghazall's Persian letters, Makdtib, p. 19, line 8; cf. German tr. in D.
Krawulsky, Briefe und Reden des Abu Hamid Muhammad al-Gazzdli (Freiburg im Breisgau:
K. Schwarz, 1971), p. 91. In Mishkat, part 1, §43, p. 17, line 3, '... and His Face' is added
(see paraphrase below). See also al-Ghazali, Kimiyd, 'onvdn 2, fast 8, vol. 1, p. 62; and the
important passage in al-Ghazall, Maqsad, p. 58, lines 7ff. (quoted in B. Abrahamov, 'al-
Ghazall's Supreme Way to Know God', Studia Islamica 77 (1993), pp. 141-68, at pp. 159f.).
According to Landolt, 'Ghazall and Religionswissenschaft', p. 60, n. 161, the phrase 'there is
nothing in existence save God' is a 'famous dictum summarising ontological tawhid,
attributed by 'Ayn al-Qudat to Ma'^ruf al-Karkhl {Tamhiddt [ed. 'Oseyran, Mosannafdt-e
'Eynolqoddt-e Hamaddni (Tehran: Daneshgah-e Tehran, 1962), p.] 256)'. He goes on to say
that others, like Najm-e RazI and SemnanI, attribute it to Junayd (citing Der Islam 50 (1973),
p. 56). See also W.C. Chittick, 'RumI and wahdat al-wujUd' in A. Banani et al. (eds). Poetry
and Mysticism in Islam: The Heritage of Rami (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1994), pp. 70-111, at p. 71; p. 105, n. 4 with further references; I am indebted to Kazuyo
Murata for bringing Prof. Chittick's article to my attention. The historicity of the attribution of
this phrase to such early authorities as Ma'ruf al-Karkhl or Junayd is however somewhat
suspect. Junayd's discussion of tawhid (A.H. Abdel-Kader, The Life, Personality and Writings
of al-Junayd (London: Luzac, 1976), pp. 68-75 and Arabic part, pp. 51-7) although
fascinating in its own right, makes no reference to this phrase or idea. I am grateful to Prof.
Gerhard Bowering for discussing this point with me and providing important references on the
history of this idea in the Sufi tradition.
It should also be mentioned that in less esoteric contexts al-Ghazall uses the fuller formula
'There is nothing in existence save God and His acts' {taysafi'l-wujUd ilia'lldh wa-afdluhu),
speaking, as it were, from the point of view of the third degree of tawhid (e.g. al-Ghazali,
Jawdhir, part 1, ch. 3, p. 11, lines 1-2; Maqsad, p. 58, lines 9-10; Mustasfd, muqaddima,
da'dma \,fann 2, imtihdn 2, vol. 1, p. 69, lines 11-12; cf //^>'a^ bk 31, vol. 4, p. 38, lines 5-6
('There is none in existence save God, his attributes and his acts'); Ihya', bk 36, vol. 4, p. 452,
penultimate line (God's essence and acts are the only existents)). Yet, the problem of how the
shorter formula, expressing the fourth degree of tawhid, is to be interpreted still remains. (On
the four degrees of tawhid see below.)
13 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 1, §41, p. 16, line 8. The entire passage is given in a paraphrase
below.
14 On al-Ghazall's view of tawhid see also: M.M. al-Misbahi, 'al-Ghazdli bayna wahdat al-
tawhid wa-wahdat al-aliadiyya' in M.M. al-Misbahl, Daldldt wa-ishkaldt: dirdsdt fi'l-falsafa
al-'Arabiyya al-Islamiyya (Casablanca: Manshurat 'Ukaz, 1988), pp. 85-112, esp. pp. I04ff.;
M. Noor Nabi, al-Ghazdli's Conception of tawhid: An Analytical Approach (Aligarh: n.p..
20 Journal of Qur'anic Studies
that Sufi terminology is introduced with some reservation and explained in terms of al-
Ghazali's own theory. Moreover, the ending 'obliteration in tawhld' was probably added by
al-Ghazali himself to make the Sufi term closer to his own. Cf. al-Ghazali, Mishkdt, part 1,
§48, p. 18 (paraphrased in note 32 below); Makdtib, p. 18, lines 21-2; Krawulsky (tr.), Briefe
und Reden, p. 90 (the Sufis are called ahl-e basirat).
28 In the Mishkdt, al-Ghazali calls this 'pure singularity' {al-farddniyya al-mahda)
{'istaghraqu bi'l-farddniyya al-mahda' (part 1, §45, p. 17, lines 16-17); 'al-mustaghriq bi'l-
fardaniyya' (part 1, §57, p. 21, line 12); cf. part 1, §54, p. 20, line 20). He clarifies that the
realm of singularity {mamlakat al-farddniyya) is the end of the creatures' ascent {muntahd
mi'rdj al-khala'iq) {Mishkdt, part 1, §55, p. 21, line 1; §57, p. 21, line 18), since any ascent
presupposes plurality, and in the realm of singularity all plurality is abolished {Mishkdt, part I,
§55).
29 Al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 35, vol. 4, p. 344, lines 2-3. On the use of the image of a 'flash of
lightning' in this context cf. references given in B. Abrahamov, Divine Love in Islamic
Mysticism: The Teachings of al-Ghazali and al-Dabbagh (London and New York:
RoutledgeCurzon, 2003), p. 65; p. 68; p. 160, n. 90; p. 160, n. 102; al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 21,
baydn 8, vol. 3, p. 26, lines 2 3 ^ ; vol. 3, p. 27, lines 26-8.
30 The subjectivistic interpretation is favored by W.M. Watt, 'A Forgery in al-Ghazali's
MishkatT, Journal ofthe Royal Asiatic Society (1949), pp. 5-22, at p. 16, and AbO'l-'Ala'
"Afifi in the introduction to his edition of the Mishkdt, pp. 15-16, among others ('Afifi claims
that this is only how mystics see things, it is wahdat al-shuhud, not wahdat al-wujud). For the
objectivist interpretation proposed here see, e.g., F. Shehadi, Ghazali's Unique Unknowable
God: A Philosophical Critical Analysis of Some ofthe Problems Raised by Ghazali's View of
God as Utterly Unique and Unknowable (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1964), p. 32, n. 4.
31 See note 27 above.
32 Al-Ghazali, Makdtib, p. 19, lines 15-20; Krawulsky (tr.), Briefe und Reden, pp. 91-2. In
the first part of the Mishkdt al-Ghazali argues along similar lines: 'The ecstatic
pronouncements of al-Hallaj, al-Bistami and their likes are due to intoxication {sukr) and
passionate love {'ishq); these people do not reach real union {haqiqat al-ittihdd), which is
impossible, but what resembles union {shibh al-ittihdd)' {Mishkdt, part 1, §46). The correct
term to describe this state is, in relation to the person who attains it, 'obliteration' (fand') or
rather 'obliteration of obliteration' {fand' al-fand'); and in relation to That in which he is
immersed {al-mustaghraq bihi), tawhid {Mishkdt, part 1, §48; Buchman mistranslates 'in
relation to the one immersed in it', taking bihi to refer to the state {hdla), which is impossible
grammatically as well as from the point of view of the content, since al-Ghazali is
distinguishing here between sahib al-hdla and al-mustaghraq bihi, and they cannot both refer
to the person who attains the state). For a similar interpretation of al-Hallaj and al-Bistami see
also al-Ghazali, Maqsad, p. 139; and cf al-Ghazali, Fadd'ih, p. 109 where several groups who
believed in hulHl, including the ecstatic Sufis, are discussed. Cf al-Ghazali, Munqidh, §96, p.
102 for implicit criticism of ecstatic Sufis; Mizdn, ch. 4, p. 207, lines 7-14 (taken out in the
corresponding discussion in Ihya', bk 21, baydn 4); Ihyd', bk 30, baydn 2, vol. 3, p. 556, lines
6ff.
33 The text is not clear: '« khud gasht' (Krawulsky translates: 'dass sie selbst vergingen'). I
suggest amending it to 'u khodd gasht', 'he became God'.
34 See, e.g., al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 35, baydn 2, vol. 4, p. 343, lines 14ff (cf Kimiyd, bk 38,
ch. 2, vol. 2, pp. 532f); bk 36, baydn 8, vol. 4, p. 444, line 28 to p. 445, line 5 (and cf Iqtisdd,
Introduction, p. 4, lines Iff); Imla", p. 309, lines 26-9; Maqsad, p. 58, line 9 to p. 59, line 2
(quoted in Abrahamov, 'Supreme Way', pp. 159f, esp. p. 160, n. 87). In the Maqsad al-
Ghazali argues that everything is God's acts, but insofar as they are God's acts, produced by
the divine power, they are inseparable from God, just as the light of the sun is inseparable
from the sun. (On the image ofthe sun and its rays see note 71 below.)
22 Journal of Qur'anic Studies
35 Al-Ghazali, Makdtib, p. 20, lines 3-19; Krawulsky (tr.), Briefe und Reden, pp. 92-3.
36 Cf al-Ghazali, Mishkdt, part 1, §§38-9 for a shortened version of this parable (omitted in
the paraphrase cited here).
37 Note the rhetorical background of the terms musta'dr and majdzT, both meaning
'metaphorical'. I am grateful to one of the reviewers for pointing this out in his or her
comments.
38 See, e.g., R. Gramlich, 'Mystical Dimensions of Islamic Monotheism' in A. Schimmel
and A. Falaturi (eds). We Believe in One God: The Experience of God in Christianity and
Islam (London: Bums and Oates, 1979), pp. 136-48 and Chittick, 'Rumi and wahdat al-
wujud', pp. 70-1.
39 For the following discussion of Avicenna's quiddity/existence distinction and the proof
for the existence of God see, e.g., H.A. Davidson, 'Avicenna's Proof of the Existence of God
as a Necessarily Existent Being' in P. Morewedge (ed.), Islamic Philosophical Theology
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1979), pp. 165-87; M.E. Marmura, 'Avicenna's
Proof from Contingency in the Metaphysics of His al-Shifd", Mediaeval Studies 42 (1980),
pp. 34-56.
40 Cf al-Ghazali, Maqsad, section on the name al-nur, p. 157, line 15 to p. 158, line 4; H.A.
Davidson, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories ofthe
Active Intellect, and Theories of Human Intellect (New York and Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1992), pp. 132f, p. 142.
41 Notice how the question of creation becomes irrelevant in the monistic paradigm. What
matters is that created existents are perpetually perishing (both 'before' - if this is a
meaningful expression - and after creation); it is their eternal 'possible' nature that comes to
the fore.
I disagree with Davidson's interpretation {Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect, p.
133), according to which this passage implies preetemity of the world. In my view, the
passage takes no stance on the question of preetemity; rather it presents it as irrelevant.
Significantly, in the Maqdsid, Metaphysics, p. 68, al-Ghazali reinterprets the term muhdath
('originated') as mumkin al-wujud, following Avicenna: 'wa-qad dhakarnd anna'l-mumkin Id
yakHnu mawjUdan bi-nafsihi bal bi-ghayrihi wa-hddhd ma'nd kawnihi muhdathan, fa'l-'dlam
idhan mumkin al-wujUd fa-huwa idhan muhdath, wa-ma'nd kawnihi muhdathan anna
wujudahu min ghayrihi wa-laysa lahu min dhdtihi wujQd, fa-huwa bi-i'tibdr dhdtihi Id wujUd
lahu wa-bi-i'tibdr ghayrihi lahu wujQd, wa-md li'l-shay' bi-dhdtihi qabla md lahu bi-ghayrihi
qabliyyatan bi'l-dhdt, wa'l-'adam lahu bi'l-dhdt, wa'l-wujud bi'l-ghayr, fa-'adamuhu qabla
wujudihi, fa-huwa muhdath azalan wa-abadan li-annahu mawjUd min ghayrihi azalan wa-
abadan'. Cf Avicenna, Ddneshndme-ye 'ald'i: eldhiyydt, ed. M. Mo'in (Tehran: Anjoman-e
Athar-e Milli, 1952), §28, p. 83, lines 4-5: 'momken ol-vojud rd vojUd be-'ellat bovad va be-
khud a rd hasti nabovad va be-chizi digar-ash hasti bovad, va mohdathi in bovad'.
42 This has already been noticed by Landolt, 'Ghazali and Religionswissenschaft', p. 61.
43 Avicenna, al-Shifd': al-ildhiyydt, ed. G.C. Anawati et al. (Cairo: Wizarat al-Ma'arif
1380/1960), bk 8, ch. 6, pp. 356, lines 10-15. The importance of this passage for al-Ghazali
was already noticed by R.M. Frank, Creation and the Cosmic System: al-Ghazdli & Avicenna
(Heidelberg: Carl Winter Universitatsverlag, 1992), p. 16; p. 62, n. 118. Other relevant
passages in Avicenna include: Ildhiyydt, bk I, ch. 8, p. 48, lines 5-13; bk 8, ch. 3, p. 342, lines
6-14; Commentary on Metaph. Lambda, ad 1072b3 in 'A. Badawi (ed.). Arista 'inda'l-'Arab
(Kuwait: Wakalat al-MatbO'at, 1978), pp. 22-33, here p. 25, line 23 to p. 26, line 2 (alluding
to Q. 28:88; at p. 26, line 2 read 'wa-fkdsij al-ashyd' al-ukhrd haqiqat wujudihd', following
Cairo, Dar al-Kutub, MS Hikma 6M, fol. 139v.; I am grateful to Prof Dimitri Gutas for kindly
providing me with a copy of the manuscript and to Prof Jules Janssens for confirming the
reading); Commentary on the Theology of Aristotle in Badawi, Aristu 'ind al-'Arab,
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazall's Mishkat al-anwar 23
pp. 35-74, at p. 46, lines 5-9. On the First Cause as pure self-subsisting light see also
Avicenna, Commentary on the Theology of Aristotle, pp. 56-7 (already discussed by
Davidson, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect, pp. 132f).
44 Here and below notice Avicenna's puns on the root /i-^-^.
45 Al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 35, bayan 2, vol. 4, p. 343, line 13 and elsewhere, e.g. bk 36, baydn
8, vol. 4, p. 444, line 29; vol. 4, p. 445, line 2; Mishkdt, part 1, §45, p. 17, line 15; part 2, §26,
p. 30, line 15; part 3, §33, p. 52, line 6 (cf part 1, §42, p. 16, line 16 and part 2, §14, p. 28,
line 10: 'al-awwal al-haqq'). In the context of the third degree of tawhid God is usually called
al-wdhid al-qahhdr (the expression occurs e.g. in Q. 40:16, quoted in Mishkdt, part 1, §44, p.
17; Maqsad, p. 160). See Ihyd\ bk 35, baydn 2, vol. 4, p. 342, line 9; p. 351, line 5; cf qdhir
in Ihyd', vol. 4, p. 345, line 22.
46 G.F. Hourani, 'A Revised Chronology of Ghazali's Writings', Journal of the American
Oriental Society 104 (1984), pp. 289-302, at p. 298a.
47 Al-Ghazali, Maqsad, p. 172, lines 13-14; cf the section on al-haqq in Maqsad, pp.
137ff, which is clearly modelled on the passage from Avicenna's Ildhiyydt, bk 8, ch. 6,
quoted above.
48 For Avicenna, both the Necessary of Existence and the contingent beings can be said to
exist in the proper sense (the existence of the contingent beings is not metaphorical), yet the
degree to which they 'deserve' existence differs, and hence the term existence is predicated of
them 'by gradation' (bi'l-tashkik). See the discussion of 'graded terms' {asmd' mushakkika) in
Avicenna's MaqQldt of the Shifa', ed. G. Anawati et al. (Cairo: Wizarat al-Ma'^arif,
1378/1959), bk 1, ch. 2, p. 10, line 8 to p. 11, line 4, where 'existence' is used as an example. I
intend to deal with the question of the 'gradation of existence' {tashkik al-wujUd) in Avicenna
in a forthcoming study.
49 Watt's view that the third part is not authentic (Watt, 'A Forgery in al-Ghazali's
MishkdtT) is to be rejected, among other reasons because there are (partial) parallels to this
section in other works of al-Ghazali; see Landolt, 'Ghazali and Religionswissenschaft', p. 27,
n. 34 for references, to which one can add al-Ghazali, Kimiyd, 'onvdn 2,fasl 5, vol. 1, p. 57ff.
However, as Landolt notices (p. 72), 'only a careful examination of the whole manuscript
tradition, plus extemal evidence' will be able to settle the question completely.
50 Moses' response is 'Lord ofthe heavens and the earth' {rabbu'l-samdwdti wa'l-ard) (Q-
26:24, also a grammatical iddfa in Arabic). Both Pharaoh's question and Moses' response are
quoted and discussed in al-Ghazali, Mishkdt, part 2, §15 (Passage B above).
51 It goes beyond the scope of this article to provide identifications of these groups. This
subject is in need of further study. For tentative identifications based on earlier scholarship
(Gairdner and Landolt) see Buchman's notes to his translation of the Mishkdt, p. 67, n. 14, nn.
16-18.
52 The construction nisbatu X nisbatu Y ('X is analogous to Y') is related to the more
common construction mathalu X mathalu Y ('X is similar to Y'). The reading/? instead of ild
is, as far as I know, not attested in the manuscripts of the Mishkdt; however, it seems superior,
for al-Ghazall is speaking about the rank of the angels among the intelligible lights (analogous
to the rank of the stars, the moon and the sun among the sensible lights {fi'l-anwdr al-
mahsUsa)), not about their relation to the intelligible lights, of which they, after all, form a
part.
53 Min jiha serves simply to indicate the agent of the passive participle (cf min qibal in
Modern Standard Arabic). Both Buchman {Mishkdt, p. 51) and Landolt ('Ghazali and
Religionswissenschaft', p. 41) seem to mistranslate the sentence. Min jiha in this function
occurs in Munqidh, §45, p. 78, line 7 {'bal hiya musta'mala min jihat fdtirihd') as well as in,
e.g., Ps.-Ammonius, see Ulrich Rudolph, Die Doxographie des Pseudo-Ammonios: Ein
24 Journal of Qur'anic Studies
62 Al-GhazalT, Mishkdt, part 2, §14, p. 28. My paraphrase here clears some inaccuracies of
Landolt's paraphrase quoted in note 58 above. First, al-Ghazali, strictly speaking, is not saying
that the act of turning the face is 'undetermined' but rather that 'He who' is an unspecific
reference. Second, he is not saying that 'the concept of He who {mafhum alladhi) is, as such,
beyond any conceivable referent' but that the referent of this concept has no image {mithdl)
and does not have analogous correspondence {mundsaba) with anything else.
63 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 1, §29, p. 11.
64 On this subject see also the excellent studies by Lazarus-Yafeh, Studies, Appendix C:
'Some Notes on Al-Ghazzall's Cosmology', pp. 503-22; K. Nakamura, 'Imam Ghazali's
Cosmology Reconsidered with Special Reference to the Concept of jabaruf, Studia Islamica
80(1994), pp. 2 9 ^ 6 .
65 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 2, §§9-10, p. 27.
66 Al-Ghazall, Mishkat, part 2, §9, p. 27.
67 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 1, §31, p. 12.
68 Al-Ghazall, Mishkdt, part 2, §17, p. 29. Admittedly, the term mundsaba is not used in this
passage, but the context, explaining how images are coined, suggests that this discussion
applies to cosmological images as well. The term mundsaba does occur in a parallel, but more
extended, discussion of dream interpretation in al-Ghazali, Ihyd', bk 40, ch. 8, vol. 5, p. 204,
line 5.
69 This is an allusion to the hadith 'the veridical dream is one forty-sixth part of prophecy'.
70 On the correspondence in ma'nd ruhdnl see al-Ghazali, Faysal, ch. 4, in the discussion of
the five levels of existence, on the intellectual existence of the 'Hand' of God: 'wa-man qdma
'indahu al-burhdn 'aid istihdlat yad li'lldh ta'dld hiya jdriha mahsusa aw mutakhayyala fa-
innahu yuthbitu li'lldh subhdnahu yadan ruhdniyya 'aqliyya, a'ni annahu yuthbitu ma'nd al-
yad wa-haqiqatahd wa-ruhahd, duna suratihd, inna ruh al-yad wa-ma'ndhd md bihi yabtishu
wa-yafalu wa-yu'ti wa-yamna'u, wa'lldh ta'dld yu'tl wa-yamna'u bi-wdsitat mald'ikatihi'
(p. 36).
71 Notice also the striking phrase 'There can be no reference to the light of the sun but only
to the sun. Now, everything in existence relates to [God] as light relates to the sun' (al-
Ghazali, Mishkdt, part 1, §54, p. 20, lines 17-18, at the end of Passage A). The image of the
sun and its rays is used by al-Ghazali in several works (see, e.g., the reference to the Maqsad
in note 34 above), usually in implicit parallel to God and His Face: just as the sun cannot be
said to be greater than its light so also God cannot be said to be greater than His Face.
Compare e.g. the following passages on the meaning of 'God is greater' {Alldhu akbar): (1)
'The meaning of Alldhu akbar is not that He is greater than other things, since there is nothing
else beside Him {bd vey) for Him to be greater than it, for all existents come from the light of
His existence [just as] the light of the sun is nothing but the sun and /; is impossible to say that
the sun is greater than its light. Rather the meaning of Alldhu akbar is that He is too great to
be known by humans through rational inference {qeyds-e 'aql)' {Klmiyd, 'onvdn 2, fast 8, vol.
1, p. 62, lines 17-22); (2) '[The knowers] do not understand the meaning of Altdhu akbar as
implying that He is greater than something else, God forbid, since there is nothing else beside
Him {ma'ahu) for Him to be greater than it. Anything other than He does not have the rank of
withness {ma'iyya) but the rank of following {taba'iyya). Moreover, anything other than He
exists only with respect to the Face adjacent to Him. Therefore only His Face exists. It is
impossible to say that He is greater than His Face. Rather the meaning of [Alldhu akbar] is
that He is too great to be called "greater" in the sense of relation or correspondence {bi-
ma'nd'l-iddfa wa'l-muqdyasa) and too great for another to grasp the utmost limit of His
magnificence, even be he a prophet or an angel' {Mishkdt, part 1, §44, p. 17, lines 5-11; cf
also Arba'in, bk 2, ch. 6, pp. 73-4).
26 Journal of Qur'anic Studies
72 The possibility that al-Ghazali followed Avicenna in believing that God has no quiddity
other than existence has to be taken seriously. In the Maqdsid, for instance, al-Ghazali says
that it is because God has no mdhiyya that He cannot be known through rational inference
{qiyds) {Maqdsid, p. 97, line 2ff.). Admittedly, Maqdsid is an Avicennian work, largely based
on Avicenna's Ddneshndme (see J. Janssens, 'Le Danesh-Nameh d'lbn Sfna: Un texte a
revoir?'. Bulletin de philosophie medievale 28 (1986), pp. 163-77); however, this passage
does not seem to have a correspondence in the Ddneshndme and is, in all likelihood, al-
Ghazali's own addition. This subject requires further study.
73 Al-Ghazali himself draws a distinction between these two ways. In the first part of the
Mishkdt (part 1, §45), al-Ghazali states that there are two ways toward the realisation that
'There is nothing in existence save God'. Some of those who see only God in existence
arrived at this realisation through a scientific cognition {'irfdnan 'ilmiyyan), others - through
an experiential state (lit. 'state of tasting', hdlan dhawqiyyan, cf. Mishkdt, part 3, §33 quoted
below). I prefer not to translate 'irfan as 'gnosis', since this may be misleading. For this term
see Mishkdt, part 1, §66, p. 24, line 10, where it obviously means 'cognition' and has no
mystical connotations.
74 Al-Ghazali, Mishkdt, part 3, §§31-3, p. 51, line 17 to p. 52, line 8. Some of the elect
among the elect (4.2), al-Ghazali continues, reach this realisation gradually like Abraham,
others instantaneously {dufatan) like Muhammad.
75 Notice the contrast between the experience of jaldl here and the experience of jamdl by
the previous group (4.1).
76 Al-Ghazali, Munqidh, §96, p. 103, line 1, 'wa-kana md kdna mimmd lastu adhkuruhu /
fa-z,unna khayran wa-ld tas'al 'ani'l-khabari'. The verse is by Ibn Mu'^tazz (metre: al-basit).
11 On 'ilm and dhawq see, e.g., Abrahamov, 'Supreme Way', pp. 165f.; M.E. Marmura,
'Ghazali and Ash'^arism Revisited', Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 12 (2002), pp. 91-110, at
pp. 97ff.; R.M. Frank, 'Al-Ghazali on Taqlld: Scholars, Theologians, and Philosophers',
ZeitschriftfUr Geschichte der arabisch-islamischen Wissenschaften 1 (1991-2), pp. 207-52, at
pp. 216ff.
78 This subject will be treated in greater detail in my forthcoming PhD dissertation on al-
Ghazali's metaphysics, directed by Prof. Dimitri Gutas.
79 To the best of my knowledge, this process has not been sufficiently documented and
analysed. A careful study of it would be an important contribution to the history of Sufism and
Islamic thought as a whole.
80 Al-Biruni's India was completed in 421/1030, shortly after the death of his patron
Mahmud of Ghazna. See C. Edmund Bosworth et al., art. 'Biruni' in Encyclopaedia Iranica,
vol. 4, pp. 274-87, at p. 275b.
81 Al-Biruni, Alberuni's India: An Account of the Religion, Philosophy, Literature,
Chronology, Astronomy, Customs, Laws and Astrology of India about A.D. 1030, ed. Edward
Sachau (London: Trlibner, 1887), ch. 3, p. 16. I owe this reference to William Chittick's
article, 'Rumi and wahdat al-wujud', pp. 104f., n. 3, where this passage is partially translated
and briefiy discussed. On comparable doctrines on the Indian side see al-Biruni's discussion
in his India, ch. 2. One thinks especially of the Advaita Vedanta (not, however, mentioned by
al-Biruni). A very brief and insufficient analysis of al-Biruni's presentation of Indian monism,
in comparison to Advaita Vedanta is offered by H. Heras, 'The Advaita Doctrine in Alberuni'
in Al-Birunl Commemoration Volume, A.H. 362-A.H. 1362 (Calcutta: Iran Society, 1951), pp.
119-23.
82 The form of this term as given by al-Biruni is in fact Syriac, not Greek.
83 The 'porch' was part of the mosque in Medina, where the pious 'people of the porch'
reportedly lived at the time of the prophet. For the translation 'porch' (as opposed to the more
common but incorrect 'bench') see Lane's entry in his Arabic-English Lexicon (Beirut:
Monism and Monotheism in al-Ghazall's Mishkat al-anwar 27
Librairie du Liban, 1997), bk 1, pp. 1693-4: 'An appertenance ofa house ... or ofa building,
like a wide bahw [...a kind of vestibule, or portico, for shade and shelter, open in front] with
a long roof or ceiling'; the suffa of the mosque of the Prophet was 'a covered place, an
appertenance of the mosque, ... roofed over with palm-sticks'. See also W.M. Watt, art. 'Ahl
al-suffa' in Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2""* edn.
84 On this trend in early Sufism, see the references cited in note 38 above.