Ross 1967 Constraints On Variables in Syntax
Ross 1967 Constraints On Variables in Syntax
SUMES
ED 016 965 AL 000 976
CONSTRAINTS ON VARIABLES IN SYNTAX.
BY- ROSS: JOHN ROBERT
MASSACHUSETTS INST. OF TECH., CAMBRIDGE
PUB DATE SEP 67
EDRS PRICE MF-$2.66 HC- $21.00 523F.
11." by
%4C)
III
w
r-4 J0414 ROBERT ROSS
U)
B.A., Yale University (1960)
POSITION OR POLICY.
at the
a .....
"PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE THIS
delnatito MATERIAL HAS BEEN GRANTED MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF
BY 1/1-4411.4226_ TECHNOLOGY
Signature of Author
Department of Modern Languages, August 21, 1967
Certified by
Thesis Supervisor
ii
DEDICATION
To four of my teachers.
to aly mother,
At,
iii
by
ABSTRACT
FRAGESTELLUNG
very convincing ring to it, Mr. James, butit's wrong. I've got a
of a giant turtle."
very good question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an
answer to it. And it's this: the first turtle stands on the back of
James patiently.
down."
5
vi
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
many teachers and administrators who have gritted their teeth and
friends I can only offer this thesis, in the hope that it. will
,
vii
period of my life;
neglected my job;
it;
summer in 1965;
fure with great pleasure that I thank Ellie Dunn, Patricia Wanner,
and, because she did the bulk of it with a speed.and industry which
were incredible, especially Lorna Howell. The care and accuracy with
of Harvard, for the care that he has devoted to reading, and commenting
on, various papers of mine, some related closely to the thesis, some
not, and for the many deep insights into syntax that his comments
afford.
could break out of the becalmed state I had gotten into. Without
his generosity, the thesis would not have been finished this summer.
2), it is doubtful
had formulated the A-over-A principle (cf. Chapter
this thesis is
whether I would have even noticed the problems which
from the great amount I have learned from his work, has also taught me
proofread the thesis, for all of which I thank him. Bruce Fraser
the theory of variables reported here and almost all facets of the
down into deeper and deeper layers of turtles. Where I can remember,
ask him to accept this general word of thanks for all the places I
have forgotten.
are as necessary as air or water, I thank our cats Krishna and Aristotle
,,Mor.r777.-nw7,77.7. c,,,07:77.774777,77"--
+
xi
new son Daniel. Erik I owe the added impetus that pushed me to finish
the thesis this summer. The ease with which this three-month-old
ti
child dislodged the completion of the thesis from its central position
cease.
The writing of this thesis has been as much of an ordeal for her as
it has for me, for which I beg her forgiveness. For making my life
as easy as it could be, under the sword of Damocles, I thank her with
my heart.
xii
Table of Contents,
.Dedications
Abstract
Acknowledgements.'Vi
10 OOO 1 Introduction
12
O
11.4bOOc OOOOOO .7
12.. OOOOOOO . 10
20 OOOOO
2.1......4.0..... OOOOO .... OOOOO OOOOOO .14
:
2.2.. OOOOO 00000006 OOOOO OOOOO .16
OOOOOOOOOOOOOOO 24
dko.0;46000040 OOOOO OOOOO
OOOOO ........ 25
25
OOOOOO OOOOOOOOO 0000000600400000000000008 OOOOO 9050 OOOOOOO
0. OOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOO OOOOO 26
2.4.1 OOOO OO OOOOOO
Tree Pruning
OOOOOOO OOOOO O
ft 4
31100 OO
s
30002O.000646066.00046000000011410004000600006600606**040000,0400060M0645
301006.1.06000000040000.000040004.04600041444.40000047
OO 47
3oldele o e "1/
o ..
3,11.3. ................51
3.1.1.2. o 49
3113. .51
e ._.0
31.1.3.2 . . . e62
301010303.00000$0,000000000000.006.0600000.000000000066606.001T00,69
3,191.4,.......,..0.0.....73
3.1.3..-,00o80
3.1.4.,0 OO .:.88
316e*00494
OO
4 00117
Footnotes....
c4}.`
4'74 1,, .0
-..=11111111
, ..
ATX
811O0001000080900000090110000110000001001100006600106011000.000.0..0041016,1
mpoom55olo1100550,WV110V orroosiposesesso4ripooloo,000m000mibo5
. . .
9n60400000600000000000.0000006.0000000000000401,004100000411000001010V
OOOOOOOOOOOOOOOO e1.
050111.0. 6E10
',Iry ,-,,........... 00,1000114b04111141100001004,94
. ..
'
7-......_S
L
coe.o.e,59Tv 89,T.....0..
sw..............99.......................,....................L.T.v
...
1p Z 8cr0000mIll0000mee011ooewoo0500055560)010o0e000041000100WITI
Niy 1 T9T600800006011011100000080000000008,111C000040006006100000000060,041z.
P
1.918,111004,1i000101000000950000000000000000000000011100000666W.500E0z0",
itr0000rnowillowomoosogoome1wor000romose00050000***00eVozo
- f
1711000110000000000001100000050000000.0006011606606660606066.4poitvorly
.
811
O0000,0#000000000000000050000000000)0000.01100000000000000801116z1,
98.1154,000000060601119000110410000000006000000051100000000000000eSSOCIOVV
s6Teeet0940004,e00000006*,000e0WO*110410900441o6011wooso*04100rnson
961
666664060606011141666004004)0041001111101,0601000WISi90411410411111411006.000TOCO
90V00000000011100,00.00410111000540004190.0091114)00000000000000041TOCO
o5114114ioefornIs09140**0.00004,004oVies ** 0 ** 90z000s000rnott000mornee
LI.c.6410000011101941000**90414,4)000000000410:0000004000410009,0044041006zizerill
EzzeiglowomeormoomIwo4,61504b000m04,414100,041Wern0400400Eorco
8ul,000041000410004,0000000411000000001100041004111.541501900000414,4144000v0Vril
Z £9
060411.04,000000110990111600400111,000900000004000000000000401100001110SOZOV
''..
,..4.--0' ,...,,..,
t:
XV
436304100410414100000041000000414100000000000.41.411060000004044000006410600240
4.4.1...o....m....woesmoososooioessooyogoomeessoossisoo.o241
4.42most0000seees*Ioeoosoeosomooses0000000*44,.....essoseooses24.5
.
404.0300690000041004100410000041041000440410044004100041000,0.41410041004104100000252
405o64141041000004104100000000 0044000000000004100000410414,410416041000.4104141000255
50
Footnotes.... c0256
5; 1 Bounding,soeeasowase
..... .
267
5.1.1.1,0268
501010000000000,04400410000000440041000410030000000000000004100040041o410.26 8
5.112e260
54296
5.113I04,...285
.11
50102090009000000000084100410414141410000944004100400,000000000000000410041,96298
5010201000000:*000004110000440041004100100000000000000414144000000000000.0298
5010202041004100041000.440000000.0441410000410000041000000410041000000041990.301
50102.3000040,4000.00000.000.444400004141000440.44444404141041444144440040041.440000306
5.103.6eolosomos000m0000o0.6o0ososoos**secom00000s00000soo..*6312
it
5.1.3.20:318
5010.3.1000000004100041410004141410410,000410410410004100000000000600000000312
5.1.321,318
5.1.3.2.2:322 .
47:77 ,77i77,77017g.""77""
, '4- .
71.
rzecTes
47zvrc
IIsozorrs
9zrts
lerc
izs,
0Trs
.
'.
te puvutta03
e too
0111114
IP,
50
*
so oo
... . .. G££..
.3 .
I
.IIII
000 f.41194
.
vcc
.0 05
I,'
.
35
8CE
sEr
BEE
TAX
SZEO
6zt
Icy
Evc.zzes
*Terris, II O sEt
oe
I II ice
ezerrig .. 0,Ke
*'
crs
Tcrs
zErs
. . ..
GOO
0. f, 1
ItC
L9E
zst
0Es
I .
. I.
uotwenlympuouola:
.
.. . vsE
ipsE
meg
.04, I
rCS .
.
crs . . .
IS II II
. I
fist
4
40 sce.
e 4p. . . .. C9C
00Erg O. G I II . C9C
'Eci. 0 4
.... . 479E0
OzEEs, I o .. g9C
.
.Ecrs
fetrs
. . . . ..
II
. L9E .
89E0(10,11
xvii
5.3040080000,00.0000.040000000000000000,000004100000000.4,000,0000094369
.
.
..
4 ........ ,
,
5040,10i 00040W,00000000008000010004.0011,0000.i00000000004.110.00.000.372
1
6.00,0401*&.dowerneeeetroee,00,382
6.1. Some Rules'Obeying the Constraints6. 46.383
6103c4...................383
6.1.1.1...i...........e.o.......60.64........................385a
64,1,1,30
6.1.1.4
ee oP; :..388
6112....1..serne*,emernee0480386
OOOOO
i
391
64,1415 Ofieoesolo0000e 391
'itdi
60101666 .......4,394
64,1411.7.6........6..396
6.1.2.64100006011'/,.398
6120ee0398
6.102.10.00041.00000.4000008.0000000000398
6.1.2.2 ..06400
6.1.2 3
6.1.2.5...5......m....)0..406
6.1.2.6 .406
6.1.207.0.0ornowolleow.sorno.rneforneofoloos0000sossomoves..408
613:41,044:444,:e40,44, so.410
6136046a:4 .414 .
641113010000eie.. c
.4.411
.14415
6.1.3.3...........................................................416
620.:
6.2.
6.2.0....:
Chopping Rules...
IP *II IP IP IP It IP IP
6820300110000416000000000,0041.00000.00418,000000006000000000000000432
.4... .422
IP IP IP .428
6.2.4. 44441,40:orne,44434
6.20402..... .w437
...... ..........434
602.500.041100,.0,011WOMo40060411000Oplio*O0o000MOSOoOloo6000.41000.442
6114061100
6.4. Islands.... ..........................................449
3,...O0.0..00.450
6.4010.
o .4..6449
6444,10. 4e414,006646,54iiloorn450
. ,
t"; ;;.,,
&
.4!
461
xix
6.4.1.1 ..06451 . .
.,
6040164.6CO*
6.44.36.0m 006
6.4.2.
4.
.6.464
6.4.3 .6.469
6.4.3.1. .469
.477
6.5. SummarY.......0 3
Footnotes***6e6***64 .481
=10. Conclusion....
Bibliography0604 .495
Biography* .500 . ot
,...,..
Chapter 1
INTRODUCTION
has substantiated amply, to my mind, the claim that the optimal frame-
1
character, superficial (or surface) phrase mar_ kers. Within this
which makes correct predictions about strings of words not yet observed,
is not; etc..
A ,
-..tRi4
2
lying (1.1) to the one underlying (1.2)3 (here and elsewhere I will give
2 3
1 0 3 4- 2
A r .
3
(1. 1')
NP
NP went. off
,Fun VP NP
I
which I h d cleaned
n.
a gun went off NP . NP VP
which assumes (1.2') is.basic; but I will not undertake such a demon-
stration here, since the point at issue is more general, and these rules
complete analysis.
wbich would prow that (1.5) must derive from (1.4) -- some rule like
(1.6) NP V [NP S] - PP
=nneS NP OPT
3. 2 3
1 0 3 + 2
to collapse rules which are similar in certain ways, and (1.3) and,(1.6)
. ..
collapse to yield (1.7);
:
".
(1.7) [NP S]
NP PP
1
L"....see.....11 . OPT
2 3
1 0 3 + 2
more general rule, (1.10), which I will call Extraposition from NP:
[NP SI Y
NP NP OPT
1611111......vaorISIMIIIIId
1 2 3
1 0 3+ 2 ..
.,,,,r.,
4,
5
range over all strings, including the null string. With them, the
(1.11) ,
NP
r
I
s
: :, ' 1 *,
t.... :
that NP VP
./'
NP S went
7\ off
1
NP NP *-
- .-..-. ,.
which
1 :
I had
//"NN
cleanid .
. t
-. .
.:
.
(1.12) 1
NP
1
.,
.
.
4 LW
I
VP surprised : no one -which I cleaned
IL LA wtnt off
phrase, and there are a number of ways of incorporating this fact Into
.;
A-
6
. " I. "
4.1
u yr or
sentences like (1.12) , which arise because of the great power which
Such a "solution" is feasible for this rule, but any linguist adopting
it will have merely postponed the day of reckoning when he will have
the case above, with respect to the rule of Extraposition from NP.
hand):
(1.13) X NP Y
OBLIG
2+1, 0 3
" .,1111111110M
1
t: 7
variables. And yet, just as was the case with rule (1.10), Extraposition
from NP, it is easy to see that (1.13) is far too strong, for it will .
show that some rules must contain variables but that somehow the power
possibly some which are even peculiar to some rule in some particular
r
language, but I have by and large avoided detailed discussion of these
suspect to be universal.
8
study of syntax is truly 'in its infancy. But it will be seen below
that the constraints on variables which I will propose are often of such
place to limit the power of the apparatus which is available for the
coordinate structure, verb, and many others. The present work should
theory of synton for without it the most striking fact about syntactic
1,1 a.
,orocesses - the fact that they- may. operate over indefinitely large
either are most generally stated, or can only be stated, with the
its structural index will work properly until syntactic theory has
provided variables which are neither too powerful nor too weak. It
this latter course will soon come to realize that many of the constraints
subsequently proposed by him, and demonstrate that they are too strong
a number of rules and show that these rules are subject to the
.", -,....4.44±kOda474
11
Chapter 1
:. FOOTNOTES.
' :
2. For further discussion of the notions of observational and
.
" t.
"°` kk:
V
- ,f 1.
12
Chapter 2
W=m;imillmmilsWirmwW41,732,77.7wArsir4W4-707;,-;:-'
03.
41 .
13
I....
(2.1)
+ I.
s
)i 1 , I,. I .
. :
Nt ,7 '4,
1%. ,
1101 /
4 I
.
, *'
e_
t
.,-
41"4"".
14
2.3 Chomsky, in the course of revising the paper quoted aboVe for
Theory, (Chomsky 1964b), realized that the A-over-A principle was too
strong. On page 46,: in footnote 10, he gives the examples "who would
each case the question word, who or what, itself an NP, has been
are not difficult to construct, and there are even cases where the
(2.2) NP 1 .
.,,,./°"'""ft.
NP
,..-47'4,....
Det NP VP
. ,..
'' lost NP .
PP
... ..
Det N NP
r
'tLe book
9.
The relative clause rule", when applied to (2.2), will produce
either the book, the cover of which I lost, or the book which I lost
the cover of, the second of which would be ruled out by the A-over-A
,reports, the relative clause rule must produf& (at least) four
prescribes the height of the letteriagau and the reports which .'.
(cf. §4.3 below); but for the purposes of the present discussion
all but the first of these four clauses. Many other examples of
the same kind, whicL show that the principle as originally stated,
s
16
,
all of the cases but one, I will not present here the alternative
so that all cases which seem to support the A-over-A principle are
grouped together.
,
I chasedl.the boy'whothrewla snowball] at 'our .
NP NP
teacher.] can ziever be embedded as a relative
,:' :
'4 . 4 41 .
' 1 .-f .
. 1
, 4 , ; .,. i
,}C '
'
17
4.
boy who threw at our teacher.
of
Thiè restrtetion also applies to elements
f
.. 51
(i.e., those in which the
reduced relative clauses
3 the VP- bikinis , ..
initialvhich'is has been deleted ):
, .
, in the following
: 'is impossible to.question or relativik.s
. .,. .
.
:,...
ibikiniili to the police.
.
.
,
.,
,
,
4
_ :
,
:
is impossible: . :
,f .! i ,,t .
IA
,
, r,, ' , ;
4 .4
1 1,., . I, 01 ..i . .0 '
i
,. . ( ,,,....
..
I
,
. ,,,:,,.,,..,
....
.
,
st ,.:, ., . ; .. 7
18
1. .2 3
1 0 3+2
'1
'topmost cycle of the structure shown in (2.7).
.
4 ,,
$.4 .
t .5
;
.r I°,
r
>Fa1
3 1r 17.; ry ; . ,
,
+1. t
4.
" r
t r 1,14I
t. .
4
C
.
. I
tk
It
. t. .
.,,,,
r-4". ..:"" 4'1414%<,-e,Nti4
I
.-t
19
- (2.7)
'I
NP
N was 'given
(1)241,e.
"that NP
.
had been made
;
* t'
1
17 VP
4
'that
: i
.
.,.... :.;:.
.
... . .
....
,
the grammatical sentence (LS) ,
'
'0.' : .
I
.,
(2.8) A proof was given that the .claim that
e
I :1
I
;
k .
VI.'
,
.
4-
,:romossoklisem
20
rt
of how these notions could be made precise, it should
.. NP
In a relative clause structure, ie/Ss it is,
NP' S'
i.
not possible to question or rPlativize the
a.
tT trj 4.
-
1I
21
Vith: 'behind.
It
1
was acquainted with?
.,......0. . ...
.;' ' i ...
;
Determiner cannot be questioned or relativized
,
I.
":e
1141 :*' out of the NP which immediately' dominates that
,
. !..
S.
to form :(2.15)i
;r/4(f -42? ..
f: . ,
22
' .
(2.14)
NP
found Det N
./' 1
NP "bodk
.
4. a
.%
1
(2.15) * Whose did you find book ?'
, J..
. , . :
may be questioned (2.18) and (2.19) are both
." . .
." ,t4'; ,
impossible.
,. -
; ..,t.
-A principle;
ed from
the
t. ;
24
explanations for all seven of the cases discussed in 6 2.2 above. '
?I 4
sentences like (2.11) will be shown to be excluded by either of two
with relative clauses. The Pied Piping Convention will also be used
Structure Constraint.
;,
Case G remains to be explained without invoking the: ."
25
which are part of the same 111, as the N over which the adjective
1 2 3 4
1. 3 2 0 4
pointed out by EcCawley, recent work (cf. Lakoff and Ross (op.'cit.))
examples:,
,1 here, for to do so would be unnecessary for my present purpose:
suff4ce to show.
of ungrammatical sentences like * I painted red it
is too strong
that MCCawley's formulation of the Adjective Shift*Rule
and must be replaced by some rule formulated along the general lines
2.4.
InCILLl'ueltELLtieor(Chomsky (1964b))*
2.4.0.
having realized that the A-over-A principle was too strong, Chomsky
rule.
proposed two other conditions on the relative clause and question
i
t 1.
1
. 4
v 4
e .1
1' , : i
1
. ' :
'1,0
26
Chomsky at no time claims that these two conditions will have the
same coverage as the principle, but since the facts given in cases
to see how far his two conditions can go towards this end.
.; 2.4.1. .
The first of the proposed conditions on this rule is
4
S
e , "Notice that although several noun
.,,
1
Phrases in a sentence may have A attached
:4
,,. to them, the operation (6) must be limited to .
e t, ..,'.; ,.!,.
examples show that (6) cannot apply twice to
' 4 l'. ......
;
a given string as a Relativization and cannot .,
.. 1..1q. ,
,
,e ,
:'..1.;,6,,i;
,6
:;.1; :
.
, ,
once as an Interrogative transformation. Thus
if rule (6) has applied to form a string which
.
.
is embedded as a relative clause, it cannot
reapply to this embedded string, preposing one - ,..,
! ,..- of its Noun Phrases to the full sentence. Thus : :' ... '.
H
whatl', but not 'what did he wonder where John
pute'i 4tc."
. 66.......1
A./
1,
27
That is, I find the sentences in (2.23) all more or less acceptale:
, .
,,,
(2.23) au., He told me about a book which I can't
, t,
1. 4( 'whether to buy or not
, "t, . 1 ,'"
figure out how to read.
' I
H 1. `
where to obtain.
I 1 .
what to do about. ,
I i
S. ....
1 ..
41. " . 1
why he read.
figure out ?whether I should read
??when I should read.
why
c. Which books did he tell you ?whether
?when
he wanted-to read?
"* what did he wonder where John put?" is a good case in point). So,
for speakers who agree with me in finding at least some sentences like :
true. This all, indicates that much more work needs to be dons on
^'
.tv,
$
4:
6 .1
.
28
......welIt
which were discussed in 5 2.2, Condition_l can only account for case A.
10,
Condition 1 should be stated so that it will apply to embedded
.
: But in (2.25)., which has been derived from 1/.24b) through ete operation
. '
I of the Relative Clause Reduction Rule, there is no longer any wh-word
":
..;
(2.25) I knott e boy mad at John.
.
relativized. ., .
1
But thin condition is strong enough to account for cases A and (with ;,
.t 1. ;
A .
1
.1. .7-
It
,
It.
4
r
n
A 5"
29 ;:
.
suitable modification) B, of 6 2.2; an4 in fact, condition (2.26),
. .
,
It appears, therefore, that Condition 1 is of limited
..t
.41,
which will allow some of the sentences in (2.23) to be generated, but
, .
,1 '
IA
;44.4
.1''0!','. will, exclude others, like ChQmsky's example of "* what did he wonder :lc
:
:::::
?..., , -, : :. ,..
,
where,John put?''. I should add that none of the conditions I will -.... .. ..
,
..:
i'..--.,,
.,..
i..,
4
,: ",
,.,
.
', .. t: 1/4.
,.
-- .
. , .. :,..
...,. :.'
.
.
i ' .. propose in Chapters 4 or 5,can be modified, in any way, that I know
\:. ...., .,..
of, to
t e
.. . .
, .....,-
The second condition which Chomsky proposes for his rule, -:.;.-._ ,
...:.4, .
....4....,0.,.!:;.;,...;..,,...., ..
(6) . is stated as follows: ,,.....
, ..
:-..... ..,,,.:...,.,..7"..,
I: ; r -, ,-,:
: , ,,,,:tt
s.,:.. I. In i,L.;;:..ni . .
4' ' t .. .
4
,.. f a
I. 1'
. *4 1
.. V,
1-
8 n
:
.'
t j,. i' 4 ''. ft
Finally, it is clear that the first . .,
:4Vi:IA
, ,
-4-'',
,
,. ..
,..
: segment Y of the structural condition of rule ..pi .! i ,, .
.,
. .
,
,, :
A I
. , ,
. .;' : N 1 et:
i : .',.;
!,..
. ..
..f..
,.- .. have such interrogatives as 'what presumably
. . 0 "' ) ' i ' t. . '
tl" did Bill see' from 'presumably Bill saw something 9 ...--eu -
.;.s.,I.,,.:. 14 ,.t. t ., . : . ,... .
, .."
, -' , '-4 and so on. This suggests that we restrict Y .
,.4.41,-....;
..1',..--4.*:',.....
,....2:, ,..-:
.. -. .
' -"Y.i.o in (6) to the form NP + ..c. With this further
condition, we also succeed in excluding such
,
, ,
.
,,
;-,,,t' ,'. would be difficult?', although the perfectly
,, .,..;:
.. ,..,!i\:
., .
correct form 'what would it be difficult for .
.
., ..
*-...
, . , 4., % k
I i .
. . % 1
.,
.
1
.
1
o s' , t e.
, ...
, ,
. 4 i . .
. ri-
,
*;.
- !,*--
I.
, , Ai
.. I, 4. II'
* .4.
"i t 0' ' ', 1.
1
. .k 0 a . , , i !
; '
.i,
ie 7P4 . ,
.
t '
.. k 1...'', '.
' 1 ' y
L
r
.,,,,, r
?, ...?..,--
'No,..N
:1
o
: l ', ', '' ''. 30
Vf
,:t-:1`.
4 ,7,z; Aa
it.
...44*. '1
a . i
'..,.., ,
.- I
4.. :"'.r,
.
(op. cit. pp. 45-46) [I do not quote footnote
_
,
? ; lit i,-, i!..;
. .;,, 1
.,
10 here, becatise its content has been discussed
..
,,; ,,.,:l: .::;th.:
in 5 2.3. above,-an4I it. is of no direct relevance
li
-,,i I, till:, ! i".' .; ; i!zi.,41 , tc the point at hand
3.,:,.:., ,
.
, .: ,-,'
...,: ''..--,,,,:
,. :: , t, :. ,
the sentence; as was noted in footnote 8 above, questions are :c.i:1;-..,,. .
. et .7 i :' . r
i
.."
. . ..... J.
.r. :
,
4.
in Bill presumably saw something nor in Bill saw something., presumably
' ,
.
%
.
"'
'.1
"
and * what did Bill see, presumably are both probably to be -''
f `' 1.-
-,
,
I
. .. 1 .. -
I
.,. t
4. explained away, for they appear to be counterexamples.
''' 'ti
,,r ! .,:,
.
s 3:1::.,.,... ''.,-; . ,7
;. '''''i..," (2.27) After maintaining that you were sick, why did ..,... ,,. ..
:::,:,
;.-;..,;.,.'
i'''': :
;,- ,. ';! 1:,:i. '';'.1.'. (. a
1
, .p.,
,..o ' , ; I .
:1....,,,.,,
. .,., ,., .';'`1" ., .
'..., s, i'.',
--ir"'.1.',
t'l., !,.,.1.: -.
,':. ,;.''$.:'
.
-:.!..
" J IA.. .(,.
i !.. you get out of bed?
,
..-.
I
s...,.i.., :"....%;,...
,, ,... .
,
.
.
:
i..
.
,i ,
,4-.'...1
,
':. 11. ; ',:,:':' 'it ,,`,,(: 4 .:,'I'.:)i , I '. 4 :i. :,:
.. ..... ., :-.
''': . , `:' d
..,14 f, ,'...
.. , : ...r
,f : .'''' '"Y,' '1'.'
I*
. . ., , ,,, ...., .1, .,... i!, ,. is n ...; ,,,. , i.. 01,,
..t,, .
'
:It 1
4.:
41; , . ,, . ,,0.41' !, . ), y ,
... Is' -, . / . f, .
!,
. / 0 .
1, : :
s;., .. : t. ! . . .
..
.9
.. : 4.
: ,t ,;', .: !4. : ;,1,,,',
Itlii, . t,......,:.
. I
./ 1. i..
0,
.
1 ,.,
; '::. 1'''
:
.:.. .
:1'1'''''!:: ''
,..
:.7..!..2.1'''''
,....
,
. .1'; In light of
:,
longwill you ..',4';'
this promotion, how long
:: A
..,.....
' ,
..
14-. '4'44.
, ' . . ., ,v. , 61:- :c , .
;.
.' ,
:,
'''.
'',,
''' p
,
.
,
..,
-
.
;'- '
(T.
,
.. . at ' '. ...,
.
- . `
,, ;. ;. . .. ,
i 1,14 , .
:. , ...
..
4 a t . ;
;
_
44
-0 ' .. ' . . ,',.. : , .
*
I ..s ,
t"
*
'fri . 1 .).
. I
; I.,. :4 4-4...4 1 ,'' i'
, ,t .- ,* ' ; ,,..
't k ) i' ..
. 1 , .1 ' . i '',
.'
4 y .
.. q '. 4 .
. . .
.
. ' . § .. . , ' .1
4 : f
.
: ;' I ,V . . 1.
00,44.
6,4 40"
,- , 0. I '.4.4 .` 4' .- 4 481.1.1.1!
\./
'
i! .. ' 1
.i
1.
I !...
"
.
-"to * 1 .
! ' I1 I.I
:4
, ..,
i .
, * ,t
4
4
4 . .;
t
4! *V ..) .' t. 1 ; .. .3, ; :,..
.; ' ' .). '''. " I,
.4. -
, .S,A....I. ,-..4. , 31
,
t ' . ,
. .
.
.t
. .
4
stay here?
.
-; 14: ,
" Furthermore, what prompted you to hit John?
4
,41
If it rains, will you finally give up and go 1
,
,: ;, "t .,.. :it ,,'; ,.
., 't
home?
..;
,t
.; .: .,. '.5., ,.,
!
.
1 ,.:
gi
i
I
-
"
, ..., .
(2.28) A: Why, after maintaining that you were sick r, did 1'
..,11.:4!'
1.1; ,
' '
,
e ' "
"i':.. -;
,
-L,
I
. .
1",. :
4 , Now long, in light of this 1 11
Pttnaqiitifit WAAL& i
' i4 ; ' .
; .S. ,14
I
' ; ; ..; 0 0: .. , 1.
3 ":4 , . ;'' i .
4, t . `11
"."
you estay here? 1 ' .. ' .4 4. .4
-. ; n t., . ,, - .
:
.
. -
t, :..... .-.
it, 4 (.,'; X ;
4
.( ft
4
."
a r
'
' 4' . '
is one involving rule ordering,. That is one might suggest that the
t 44;`
i r
.
..
..
-
... ;.
.
.s
- -.
:%:-: f
;i
: f
e
4.1 ,
'
1
*
32
8 i 48
t
".
.
. 1
'
. .
v. 4 ., ` , . " '
1,', ' 4,'
s
never been in one. 11.? t+
` r
,ir?1 .
ss
.I: .
i. . 11
I.1 !
%I. , i
sh.
- '
'.
,
I
ir r
4 '1 s
a
sI
4 4
;
V,
I
question formation
A.
4' 4 ,4
IA .t"
,
IA
.
' '
, t it
,
"
'' . ...;*
..
, . what would you do in a typhoon, although you've never been ,'
4.:4*I
one? -'
. . y la '
,, 1st adverb movement
41 / 44
"
4
":1 v:
1"....
`' .....
'
e
s4
,,
s,.
I.
t4
i
v
s. -Z1
(2 .27)
.
*
*.
Although you've never been in one, what-would ".
:411; - you do in a typhoon ?f
4;:. ,'.4 t
4. .
2nd adverb movement
.1.;S.- .1
; "1':; 7-
.
,
i Xj
.
.
. 2.28) What, although you've never been in
. - .
.
7
r .; I a'
r-.11
Molt do 4" a typhoon?
St I I
:
e t.
be dispensed with anyway, for at the time at which the question rule - :
-
.
But there is still some doubt in my mind as to whether the rule- ,
lase
,;' were sick why you got out of bed'..
.
,4 '' ' 1 ' -' , .
. - . 4 .
i 4
.'
7", ' 1 ''''' 1"' " 'A -1a., . 4 ...",. ....
.i t' I ,, .
1 .'
, . is,
IN .
*$
'
'
4. I'
,4,..
'4,;
1
i
',., A'- 's' f $
! " 't.' "t
/44 .
s,
,s nv
.''.., .
1 i.
4,4!,
.
'0 A";
". .,
tt t,',.4 ...:q
4
1P.
'
.,f ... 1
ts
r , 04' Ov.! tiail ....,..* '
,if.',4'
:(
*0
T..:
6,:
'
.$ '1,'
4
i
6
%
:,`,4.
-.!
Y
.4,,
''
,
4' -t.i
4', 1,
r
.
,,', 7, ..,
"?
.
.
.,,: : ::3..,;'
.
.,`
. ,
,;
1
,.-
,
t.
Aso
4 . .
. 0 7
.
4 r
33
..! ,
, ,A . , : .. .
,: ..,..
,,,. ., -./"....,,...... .
. .
.
,, r, -I
1 it A
:
I
1 .4 t t .(41.t.' b. 1. ? Tom will ask you, although you've never
O
. e ':0 ?a y
. 4
,
1. ,
.;.,
y
I 7
A"
I '" .
,. ?*/ wonder, if it rains, whether he will
*, I I
c'
; .1 - finally give up and go home.
' ; . . . 1 lo,
e. '
d. *It is not known,if it rains, whether he
. .
.,t ,,t., e
, , *41 ": ,
1
,?70.
, . 4
will finally give up and go hone.
. . t.
f
e. :. *She raised the question if it
e
. rains, whether he will finally give up
'55-
and go hone.
. ,
Since the sentences in (2.30) all contain embedded '. 3-
/ ,
questions, the first adverb movement rule, which produces the sentences.:
.
of (2.27), will also generate the ones in (2.30), unless it can be t
'
1`
1, '
restricted somehow, which seems doubtful to me. And if the first
the second adverb movement rule, which Converts sentences like those
I
:.%1' when it operates on embedded questions. It does not appear to me as
,.!.
.!,,4
. .if conditions of either of these kinds on the adverb movement rules.'
-4' e
t ;
,
cannot be stated, but it does begin to seem that the rule - ordering
n: 4 .4
:.
If the correct explanation is not toibe found in the 5%44
may be necessary4.
;
r I
,g
'r
i 1;
ordering of the rules, then some version of Condition 2
i "
, I ft
I say some version", because it seems to me that the sentences in, 1
.;
I + (2.29) constitute clear (thou h rather trivial) counterexamples
5,0
I
r. I
.s
t
'
: '1" r 1
. 4,
4, .
rt. t.-4
4" ,
4.7; r. a. V .
. . ,
r
. r or oar.
,. 4.
. , 1
A
i ,5
.
-V,11-
A. ".4
I ,
V''. 4,
4,41.
'4 , ti
4
a
: I
, .
34 4
Ft
444 N
r 4,
4 ;$
.11.
:
='
04
seems perfectly acceptable, as long as heavy pauses separate
T.
,.. :
,!4,
;/. ;
.i,
' :',9:1 ' presumably, from the rest of the sentence.
(1
4
t 1 :..
;.,,.
t., P
;±k ','4,' baffling, since it seems that presumably can occur nowhere else in , ?
,
,,
'4
.ekt .., 4. .. ', ,
. : t .j .-,. 4 ..,
.
.
1
., .:,,.
..,
i
);i: :
w::..,
the questioned sentence, unless I was wrong in excluding the question 4
-
..
.,..
,Bill see, presumablz1 It is obvious that much more work will have ;
ity . ;: ;:;
to be done in this area before answers to many of the questions
I. 1
I
'
4 have raised can be attempted. "4
4
:f.,1
. re:
;` .
One last comment about Condition 2 should be made: 'I :`:: t-
:::, :. -
. - .
,' s:, , although it is strong enough to exclude Cnomsky's example, * wnat
, . :,
,
2 NI ) '
,- ,
s' :
....
, .
' l .i' I
1' '11 ' ., i "CA. ..1 14,
.
6 4.4 that sentences like this can be excluded by a' latch more ,
44
f V, ..
:,4:$14;:l.. i. ,
. . :'.. "7' .1-. .
::: .':
.:
confused mass of eases which have to do with the interrelationship '', .s.-1: '.-.
, ; ." . ti 410
. .
:,
of the tgo,adverb movement riles and the question formgtion rule. .... .
.
) , , ,
v.)
a
. ,;( 4,
.1. frw .4.3. . 44
:
'VC
,.
2.5. In summar, I have tried to demonstrate in this chapter.' e.1
that the three conditions on the relative clause and question formation
-
'c.
. .
k
; 4; . 41.
4";
. , ,
-.. ,i
`,
;...1 l' ' .4 . ,
..44i'' 1 ... .
.
' ,.
'., . .,',
"S '
.r
ft
. .
!:' . " i'
.
41
;'' ":"i
,4 .3
rf
. I
t
/. 44. $
.1
CP:
4
f
4; 1.
4i "'
4"'
1.
4. I
.
1
4
35
^
'
4 t
0.4
rule which Chomsky has proposed all suffer from defects of various
,
strong in a non-trivial way, still' is the most important of the three, . .0,1 1!%
1
, ..,
because of the wide range of cases it successfully accounts for. - , ,-
,
'.1-': %:.''
Condition 1 seems tb be somewhat too strong, in somevay which 1
AA:'.:...*Ii.i;!,'
cannot yet delimit precisely; but insofar as it is correct in the :.t.--,;4..,.n:,
, ..
.. ,..4.,.
. ., .;,,
: ;.
3 7 k ,
i.:..,
.ss!:,---1,.-;.-W, ;IY
4
t ' restrictions it imposes upon the reletivizing or questioning of .,. , ,-, .
.11 ;
-I.
' 4.
-
But it seems that this condltion, if it is to apply both to full and 'A
s
be shown in 5 4.1, (2.26) contains in rough form, the central . , ,
:
..1,t
I notion of the Complex 1P Constraint, which has much independent s 4
; 4
"
.10 'S
,
t
.,, 4
'
phenomena which way provide support for it. But whether it is
s
.
'
.
; ..
. . eventually adopted or not it can account for none of the six cases ,
t
1,.
't ;
e .-,, 1`.
I of 2:2. :'t
,
-1'
' 4
;.1
4. 4,'
I hope that in my criticisms of the three nonditions
;
.,
k 4.',
, .,
,,r
.1
4,
'el'
.. .:
'. -, -,
,
.. .,4 .
1,, s tt ,;4..., .' 14 e. 4 :-. ; ! . , , .4!.., - I ',
o
,
.0.1 kr
,- ' :,' 0 4.4 ,' '1,, 4 s
I, ,!: : 1. . .1'' '&`:. e 7 i. x. 4 ....
. ,
*4
" :, ; ' to . . `
I
7...
. /' '' .'1:''':... % ...i. ,... t : ".` k "' r
.
,
.
; .
4
o ..
.
1 . .
,...
.
. :
i , .
..,
;
, .
.1
3,
% ' . .
l ' ' ' .. .
. a . 1.
'
'81TV:es:Pt' .1,43.744e.t.y
-4es
...74 TT_8"
,
. . a
& -F
: I ' t' ,
,. .. )
4 '
; ;
,
,
, I )4 :-tt1z 4*t 4pt,, ES
1
4 t ,
jJ4ta
:
t
, l w4
I - t is 4
k
4
., . : ;
-
., .,
1 : ..
: . .' .'.:
:; 'Y ,
- : :::':: .
$1, .#J14 r
, .-t
:
S i ,
;
,
' :
, . ;,: ?
j
,.
S.. for the cOfltaXy is trtie : these conditions , in particulsr the ' , . ,
:
.,, ,. ..
'
. ':
'
' ?
kover"A principle , provide the basis fo the peaent work. For :
10 choinakf reuiarked , :. .
lii
..
; *
34
r
'tPrecisely constructed models for
%
'tTh linguistic structure can play an iinportat . '
.;
1
I t. '
deeper understanding of the linguistic data." , "
r
.
t1: , (Choineky (1957), p.5)
l
'
constraints which Will avoid the detects pointed o*t in 2.1 '
:
:
: .
z,
.. .. i J t t).
'i'
iI
£4 and will account for all the casea in 2.2. Before tU can o '
.
;:: :
. ,
':'
e
$$
be attempted, in Chapter 4, one digres8ion must intervene: "- -. b'
I
..'
:
;,...r.:
I
thapter 3, itt which the notion of tree"pruning, which interacts in
:' .; ; . ' ; '::. .
.
1 : , . '
4
: ?
c .
I , i : '
'q :
%
?
I
, 47 ' 9 41 t
, ' t , '' 'fl I
I ,? ' I :
1' 4 A
'.
I
? t
T.S 4 Ø T f .
,:
I
I ' tp;
:, ";t i
It :i 4 :; ::
1;
,
4$
4
: _ : : .
f
I -.i
' $
i4t:, "'
, l ' :
:
'i ': : : :
4 : ,
:; ;
l_ 1
' s?d. (
h ' lt h1 J, I
: LI .
! ' I - I ; .c
ii
h i 1
1
l3 1; ; (% ;;; : 44
I
b :. :
4 i:: SI
3 . ,I4 '1' -. . ' .
9'. '' .
74'J) 1.4 4 '.
. i
.
r* 4,
4
3
1
,1 . '. "
4. 7
f4f'3 13 1
4'
4'
43,
';' ,' ' :
.4 -
, I
i '4 3
4
1".
444 1 ., .
S It3 t 4
I
4
.4
4 4 41
j 4 4' ,
I
. 't k t 1.
I
.4
.., .1 t .. . -.
'. ',4' 41.-J - .4'.r ., . '.
I '.4 1.... 4. ',
5 4
-'
I S #4 3' 4 4
.4
4 .4
41
1' 1 4
5 4 * '.4 $
4 $ / .4
-
1 :" :.
: /
4 I ..
1. \
"
S.
S
4 Il
;'t .
4
4
1
S
1
4.
5
,
i
'-
4 5 44 - ..f'r 4'.
4, -
I 4
4
?/j .4
I.;., 44 I 4
4 1' 4
,
'
.4
:
117
:'''
, ,
I
4
-I ' . -
J 1
v
i
tiø-
tt,4 ;f 4' ,
I
: ;
;
;: .'
:1..: 1 '.
¶ ;
:
9 : ' ,4 '' 1
'
k
i
"? t
;tS : .. . /t'
:: .
:
: 'i 31 '?
I . . . , ', p ' ' , e '
,, - .
p , ,
: ' '
. '
44i ,;
: J .
1 .*
', u"' ::-
4 1 4
\t pit k 4 4
,
I):Iv.
.
chapter 2 , , ., '_
) I ,
+t 'a
f
' 1
( ,c ' -
1
t:
POOTNOTES ' f ' ' .
;
: .r.
; ,
r4
t't I
I.. f.,. ,
.' .''. 3 a
I '
4 * ', .. , ,,
'
% I
1',
':. ,
'
:
-. ..,' L
L& :'
1
I _ ..
I
f
a:t
I4'
:. ' "
,
; a -, j ' .'
r
,
ig the correct deep etruture of relative c1aueo , a c1im i
4\
:-
j_
'; !; ,
1I 4
I
% 4 :t . et
which is implicit in Choky' earlier discuaiica of relativi : . . ' t
# '-.' '
' _3 h -- ' .
"t$I
t, ''a t I
4
V 7
;$i c1aute (cf. Chon*ky (1964a) , p. 9O bottom, and p. 33 top) :
F -'
&g,;
; -
* 44
ta
: :
: £ r: : :; :
r;
I
y
, 'I
3j Por a discussion of tie relative c1ase reduction rule, '
I
'a l ;I $,
'i I
'a
(
I
I :: c :
_
cf. Sin:Lth (1961) . ;, ':
i;,,
: : .
q
4r :
S ' ' ' : r ,
i' I.
'U .1
t( ''.
:t
'
iI
,
I
1
;l ,t3' !' 'i
I 'j
.it !!
4. The mos t coinp].ete diacuacion of the notions P-Marker , ' / '
ci ; : "
, , ,
;d '.4'
I
1 ? ,
;g
j 1 j , ;
;t
( proDerna1ysis and a triietural index l.a contained Lu : . '
'
'
* ;
I
1 tk :
''
'ft'atl : ; 1
I
a
a
?
;, j
i
j
a'
;
) I
'
'
a a
':
\ % t
! . g P t i
a
. a
'
t
e a - '
:.
,.:
:' a ',a / . ,
-- : . -;.'
' '4.
I I -,
a,
'a -'a
I I
a '' / a
a
"
a a .
a '-
'1
a a
,
a
. :-.
1
1:
: .
a '
a
I
' I$' a
a
a l
Ut$IHSl..aI_ -
'I
£
I ':
. -
38
7. Sentences like I sainted red- all the houses which had white
They elected president a'man who had never run for public
he lives.
39
explained here.
relative clause
question mark are not quite fully acceptable; and those with
Chapter 3
TREE PRUNING1
3.0.
(3 . 2 )
VP
is Av
Adj er 'than 1i).
tall NP
Bill
what the node over the constituent than Bill (if indeed it is a
to assert that, in sentence (3.1), the single word Bill has the
makes. And yet 'in sentence (3.3), from which (3.1) is derived
since Harris (cf. Harris (1957), p. 166) have agreed that sentences
those in (3.4)
like his yellow cat, is one roughly like the one shown in (3.5).
(3.5) NP
Dec
NP VP
N Adj
Poss 'yellow,
he
(196a) and Lakoff and Ross (in preparation, b)), but at present
er......r-ropmrreroorbrpr....."'"`1,
45
thing like it into the theory, but it might be objected that (3.6)
evidence for (3.6), for in each case the rules which would be
principle are far more complex than the rules which can be
some cases extra rules would have to be added, and in one case,
cases.
cases, I would like to add one final prefatory comment, which was
and phrase is a minor one, but I feel that the contrary is the
may derive in part from the fact that such principles as (3.6)
X V Pt-t: - NP - Y
OPT OBLIG if 3 is a pronot
1 2 4 BLOCKS if 3 is "compl(
1 0 3+2 4
Boston up.
0
49
there are people who find (3.10b) perfectly acceptable, and there
may even be people who find :ct better than (3.10a) . The whole
they can be ascertained with any consistency, for this area is really
from time to time. I can only hope that most readers will share
the node S.
is
(3.10a), although the postnominal modifier'from Boston
Rule5
been pruned by (3.6) when the Relative Clause Reduction
in
A similar explanation holds for the sentences
which dominate
sentences is more acceptable, because the nodes S
strong up.
India up.
correctness of (3.6).
3.1.1.3.
the direct object has been moved to the end of the verb phrase.
destroyed:4ost of my factory.
52
condition, for the second complex NP, over which the one being
decoded.
54
to Smith.
taken.into consideration.
Dartmouth to Smith.
Smith.
worse than the b-sentences, although some speakers may find the
va, 4 U. 4
A444^.44
44G101 CM/ W V 4 %I J.i .16. G4 411.4:y
4,
4.44
444.44.
44444 W
^.44.4e,
e 444 a %.1,
44.4
ai.AM
14.4 wnmm^y4n,n1 Pt Q
and does not appear in the ones which are grammatical. Under previous
which takes a sentential object. Using the feature [4. Adj:16, the
(3.25) S
NP VP
John Au(*(MV
I
Pres V NP
I
///N.N..
r +v 1 it S
-,Adi
-,'
1 NP
be
John Aux MV
? [ +V
'happy
56
1 +v 1
it permutes over no true verb (i.e., ))unless that verb is
LAdj Ji
dominated by an NP. More formally, the rule is
X NP Y
OPT
1 2 3
1 0 3 + 2
Condition 1: 2 dominates S
2: BLOCKS if 3 = X
1
4.+V
Adj
+ X
2
J-12.
that we were it trouble a man who had a kind face? It might seem
that this sentence could be excluded on the basis of the very general
57
8
unacceptable.
necessary in any case: note that (3.27) also explains why the
b- or c-sentences.
you?
was obvious.
was obvious.
secret.
remain a secret.
left.
broke me.
broke me.
showed up pleased.
why (3,29a); (3,30a); and (3.31a) are slightly better than the
9
to be right, in many cases, I do not think it can explain the
. becoming (3.36b).
race my binoculars.
follow:
61.
He f4gwrollrhnt cint
are not sharply defined in any case, may only hold for my own speech.
62
10
will also be generated.
follow the verb of the sentence which contains them, and lowers
highly tentative, for I have not done much research on this exti:cnely
63
3. Proper names
thLreport.L available
phrases
10. Complex NP
are used instead of it. For instance, to say that direct object
kruirrONINfflimmInwvirimPonnerwr
64
unacceptable for the same reason, but (3.41) does make this claim,
(2 of (3.41)).
65
than I tried to figure out that (2 follows 4). I also find Le_ t the
dogs which are barking out (5 follows 10) somewhat better than
Knock the dogs which are barking out (4 follows 10). These two
(type 10) can precede 8 more readily than it can precede 7, and
which is the least acceptable for me, has the order 10-6; (3.40b),
which is slightly better, has the order 10-7; and (3.40c), which
order 9-4, is better than (3.13a), which has the order 10-4. The
these words must always end their VP, unless a relative clause
doesn't like.
like on.
doesn't like.
case that the ?-sentences are so bad that they should not be
through, etc. could not undergo the Complex NP Shift Rule. More
damaging is the fact that the hierarchy in (3.41) predicts that all
containing
condition which lowers the acceptability of any sentence
(3.26), Complex
of the verb watch is complex and very lengthy, rule
on (3.26).
going-away present.
in formal terms just what "near the end of an S" means, for it secns
a function.
definedwithreferencetoconstituentslikeParticle_Reduced
the amount of loss a function of the input tree and the structure
it should not have applied to, or does not apply when it should
produced 02.1QE111.115.1.1011L1:1221111.1.1.SLD, or if
intelligible (though ungrammatical); the strings produced do not
71
knowledge, I can only suggest two other rules that seem to be likely
categorically ruled out, but rather that let John out!. and a
14
young spotted doR are more natura1. So it seems to me that it
base. It has been suggested by Quine (cf. Quine (1960) p. 138) that
of the reader.
r
perfusus liquidis urget
I
odoribus
form:
(3.48) **Scrambling
NP
1
X V:
N
V
VP
1t'
N
V
Y
,
Adj Adj
Adv
`Adv
J
OPT
1 2 3 4
1 3 2 4
i dominates 3.
S
the restriction that the be in the same clause. For instance, (3.48)
as if they were in the same clause as the nouns they modify. But
note that this fact entails that node deletion has occurred, for in
clause as the noun they modify. The deep structure for (3.49) is
in Smith (1961).
(3.50)17
P
i
homB NP
....**"-- 1
'amat N7' 0
all Adj Camin am NP VP
1 1
I.
1 rNN
est bonus tla V Adj
. ..
I 1
est pulr,hra
and ma./ est from the embedded relative clauses in (3.50). If the
permute them with the elements of the main clause of t3.50), for
the adjectives would be in clauses of their own. But the fact that
and thus this fact constitutes further evidence for the correctness
of principle (3.6).
77
are far too complicated for me to even mention them here, let alone
to assign trees to the output of this rule, for the number of trees
are so different from other syntactic rules that have been studied
idiolect, which have often been grouped under the heading of stylistics;
somewhat, for it appears that languages with "free word order" may
adjectives can be permuted away from the noun they modify, this
AM.
79
that the
The skeleton for the universal scrambling rule would state
subject NP can precede or follow the VP, that the. VP can have
which exhibit "free" word-order do not all contain the same rule --
the rules in each which effect the scrambling are slightly different.
.1
80
factored out and put into a universal skeleton rule, some net4c-
the head noun of the--NP are markable, and nothing else is. In
(3.51) * homE qui est bonus amat aminam quae est ,J.chram.
The case-marking rule, which distributes the case feature with which
in order for puichra to become markable, after the alse est of the
universal.
bracketing, (3.53):
goddess.'
82
(3.53) S
NP VP
V NP
puer amat
puellam NP VP
lae Adj NP
1
est similis N
dae
to delete the alae est of the relative clause, principle (3.6) will
delete the circled node S, as was the case with the P-marker (3.50),
pi.GI,G4416 uc.c.4%.
cq1
vro.r.r, 4,-,nnrrtIntitt converted t'A'AtInM
because at the time the case-marking rule would apply, the sentence
(3.56)
puella
N
NP
i
amat Det
NP
'%, N
1
fr"iter
.1
amYcl
for the facts at present, but Postal has suggested a promising new
the noun they modify) which modify the pronoun one, and that they
one and leaves its article (i.e., he, she;ve etc.) as the only
0.
hater would change to frame, but amI would not change to amIcum
'my brother' is marked (.1.. Accusative], the rule distributing one case
NP, and the correct form, meum frarem will result. This proposal
clauses dominated by the noun phrases being marked are not markable.
I do not know whether in all case languages with a rule for reducing
be true too.
rule whose statement would require quantifiers (cf. fn. 7 above) caa
(3.58) [2 X - Y - Z [ flasylipi
1
OBLIG
1 2 3 4
1 [ 2 3 4
+casej
[4. Dative], etc.) to the entire NT, but nothing depends on this
88
what this order is is not relevant here. For example, wince the
(3.60)
89
is (3.62).
second poE lion in the most deeply embedded S. Thus unless node
be generated.
are adjoined to the right side of the first element of this sentence,
in (3..63) below.
1 2+4 3 0 5 6
in § 5.
sentences containing'as
92
like has been substituted for'as there too. Poi me, in casual
speech, (3.644 and (3.64b) are only possible with like, although
I believe the as-versions are the ones sanctioned for more formal
purposes.
the first two sentences and the last one. That is, relative clauses
93
VP
Tom
drives
the .tat
Art N V NP
1
thatman'drives
I
P ;ATP
in Art
some Ira,
this deletion, the condition ceases to be met, and the NPthat man
becomes relativizable.
among the sentences of (3.65) will not become clear until the condition
enough has been said here to prove the point at hand -- that the
should be derived from the same underlying structure, the fact that
3.1.6. The final three sets of facts which support (3.6) come
even speculate as to what the full analyses in each case are, but
merely suggest that when full analyses are.available, they will make
than on any other construction, and although there exist a wide variety
of proposed analyses to choose from (cf., e.g. Smith (1961), Lees (1961),
has been arrived at, although the range and complexity of examples
are ungrammatical, while (3.70b) and (3.72b) are not, but it does
seem likely that the eventual explanation of this fact will hinge
on the fact that the node .S which dominates the phrase that man 'is,
in (3.69a) and (3.71a) will have been deleted by (3.6) when the
S-pruning also has to do with comparatives and with the way they
the adjectives in (3.73) - (3.75) are all derived from the same
than John.
(3.75) a. * Mary has never kissed a man taller than John is.
97
(3.6) asserts that this is not the case for (3.74b), although it
is the case for (3.74a), and thus provides a basis for explaining
as John is.
as John.
which cannot be gone into here, and so little is known about them
that it may turn out that the explanation which I have proposed
for the differences between (3.75a) and (3.751%) and between (3.76a)
phonological carrier of the contrastive stress for the entire NP. And
which funderlined above, may turn out to be, it will depend to some
discussed eight cases which all support, some more strongly than
...,Tyrlrrirry-11ffr,f17111111.07471,4116
V--
100
22
Reduction which we propose there depends crucially on pruning
ones for arguing that the node NP must be deleted; and the only
Reduction Rule which will be presented in Lakoff and Ross (op. cit.),
but which cannot be gone into here. Yuki Xuroda first suggested
23
the possibility that other constituears than t might be deleted.
above), so that the case of the first can be changed, but not that of
the second, but there are problems with it aside from those mentioned
in fn. 18. Thus, presumably phrases like the brave the dead, thelust,
keep their status as an NP) even though the underlying head noun,
101
ones, has been deleted. I have no argument for this other than
by the general condition that only non branching nodes delete, the
Chapter 3
FOOTNOTES
at least.
CL94
6. Postal and Lakoff have pointed out that words which traditionally
follo /ing Lakoff (cf. Lakoff (1965)), I will designate with the
Aside from these two rules, it has previously been thought possible
105
For example, it is often said that C\e sentence Bill was sick
to (3.28a) - (3.33a).
Fillmore (1965).
Emmon Bach has recently pointed out (cf. his note "Problom-
are basic and that sentences with'to are derived from them, but
ordering below:
PPWITT'AVIIVIROMI, grarfolfprwanrIt
107
'Pronominalization
Dative
ordering is necessary:
"Dative
Pronominalization
BASE: I gave the girl who. - .wanted _the book the booki
Pronominalization
applies
(
* I gave the girl who wanted the booki its.
108
The only solution I can find within the current theory it.to
been studied
P. wide variety of cases, but which has never
verb-particle combinations:
like his yellow cat, is one roughly like the one shown in (3.5).
(3.5) NP
Det
Art Postart
()
NP VP
Adj
N Poss yellow
he
(1965a) and Lakoff and Ross (in preparation b)), but at present
:fijure'off.i'Dgure*in,0 etc.
110
end point."
IA. The most detailed treatment of this problem which I know of it
Mark Liberman has recently pointed out that the word one is
-house and/1 bought a wooden one. One can mean simply 'house,
that the input structure of.the above sentence, when one has the
theory.
112
18. Unfortunately, there are facts in Latin and Russian which will
19. It has been realized for a fairly long time that the notion
must be adopted.
to rescue.
have the same d.c.s. Several such sentences are given below.
deep structure of John knows a tall. man, the other from one
or i,
so reluctantly.
the first sentence above- them_as_ sisters. Thus they will not,
a. b. c. S
NP NP
Ivan Ivan
21. The reasons for arguing that manner adverbs are not constituents
22. This is the rule which reduces such sentences as John knows
the answer and Bill knows the answer to John and Bill know the
answer, and Otto sells Buicks and Otto sells Fords to Otto
''''' 1444u
117
Chapter 4
4.0. In this chapter and the next one, I will propose a set
will show to have roughly the same effect as the te-aver-A, principle.
transformations which have the effect of moving one or more terms of the
definition of this notion will, not be given until Chapter 6.) Two
_#PRITAWRerAttelliMPIRmIRFAMwwvirmrsownersolegmen~...
. -
WHIRMORIMONITIPPRIMIMPIWIRIPWpmspiawwwww
.
,
118
(4.1). Question
Q- X - NP Y .
OBLIG
1 2 3 4
1 1+2 n 4
W NP (s X - NP 11 -
? JNP
OBLI
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 2 4+3 0 5 6
Condition: 2 a 4
of all the other reordering transformations I know of, and show that
about is sick.
sick.
questioned or relativized.
Relative Clause Reduction Rule, the node S which dominates the clause
first suggested it, when the theory of tree-pruning was much less
120
(4.7) the man who I read that the police were going
to interrogate
(4.8)
V NP
%lad
it
and unless some way.is found of pruning the circled node S or the
121
is not feasible:
(cf. Lees and Klima (1963), Postal (1966b)); thus the fact that (4.9a)
time that this rule applies. Finally, the fact that backward
2
pronominalization into that-clauses is possible (cf. (4.11a)) also
way to save (4.5) is to claim that the boxed node NP must be deleted
underlies (4.6).
122
pruning in such a way that arty non-branching node whose head had
For there are many pieces of evidence which show that that-clauses are
sink.
been insulted.
be filled with noun phrases (cf. Lakoff and Ross (in preparation a)).
applied. Not enough is known about rule ordering at present for this
my wife buys.
NP pruning could be devised for this case too, (4.5) would not allow
and elements of full relative clauses behave exactly the same with
ungrammaticality of (4.15)),
Maxim.
Maxime.
with?
125
(4.16)).
NP object of believe has a lexical head noun in the first, but not
this hat.
wearing is red.
(4.19)
V NP
. I
believed NP .
` -=', - -
127
shown in (4.21),
(4.21) NP
Li-N
+Lex]
128
as the X's on the two arrows pointing left or right from A designate.
(Vote that (4.20) does not prohibit elements from reordering within
(4.14) on the one hand, and the abstract pronoun it of (4.13a) on the
out of sentences in construction with the first two ((4.18a) and (4.15)
to keep them distinct somehow. The featurej+ Lexical] may not turn
out to be the correct one; I have chosen it not only on the basis of
the facts just cited but also with regard to the following parallel
case in Japanese.
(4.25)
NP VP
sono NP V
NP ookii
NP
sakana
N E V
k. N
I
Relative Clause Formation Rule applies, the only apparent change that
thus appear t6at the English version of the Relative Clause Formation
be passivized, as was noted by Lees and Klima (cf. Lees and Klima (1963)).
horror show.
would be.tasty.
is no-longer relativizable.
leftwards over the coreferential pronoun it. This also explains why
the pronoun he in (4.31a) can refer to the same man as the head NP
generated.
bribed him..
3.
by the sheriff.
result.
that man
1 1
(4.35b) cannot have the same raZerent as the second one indicates that
the term 'cross over', which was used in the statement of (4.30), cannot
(4.36).
,,
135
ungrammaticality of (4.38).
child sick is
'I believed the claim that Otto was wearing this hat.'
, 8 t
syatyoo o watakusi ga sinzita boosi wa aKaie
(4.40). a. *Otto ga kabutte ita to
'*The hat which I believed the claim that Otto was wearing is red.'
in (4.41).
137
(4.41)
NP
rNP VP
Ar VP
V
1
akai
N Nrf..-/.4." V boost
watakusi sinzita
VP ri.N
Lex
NP V
koto
kabutte ita
boosi
that at the time the Relative Clause Formation Rule applies, the
major difference between this structure and the structure which results
from the deep structure of (4.39b) (the deep structure which appears
with nouns like _girl (cf. (4.15)), claim (cf. (4.18a)), kodomo 'child'
(but cf. fn. 8), although there are problems with it even in English.
squandered the.money.
$400,000.
to $400,000.
and many speakers feel that while (4.43a) nay not be fully grammatical,
hopes
(4.45) a. The money which I have that the
a feeling
company will squander amounts to $400,000.
be correct, i.e., that (4.20) can be preserved as is. I have not yet
connection with this alternative, and it is only in the hope that the
(4.46) a. I snoozed.
b. Sam progressed.
and (4.47)),
(4.48) a,3 S
VP
'
I V
1
snoozed
b.
NP VP
I V NP
took a
snooze
142
contains only one NP, but the one in (4.48b) contains two, so
relation which converted the former into the latter (the opposite
theory of generative grammar, one could only claim (a) that the
(4.49)
IP
I NP
took S
'it IP
YP
I V
I
snooze
9
abstract pronoun, it, and the indefinite article would be segmentalized ,
(4.47), it should also be adopted for expressions like make the claim
that S, have hopes that S, have a chance to VP, etc., which were
both sentences in (4.42) would come from roughly the same deep
structure, (4.50).
(4.50)
r
NfP
I am
making NP
discussing
the N
andered
,
-....... 4-4,......-.
for how can this difference be accounted for, if both sentences have
about the sentences in (4.42a) and (4.45a) which sets them off from
to them. George Lakoff has pointed out to me that the rule which
a verb cannot apply if the verb has been substantivized. So, while
(4.52) is possible.
difficult.
constructions like make the claim that S, have hopes that S, etc.
the money.
money.
145
the money.
which are related to transitive verbs cannot occur with a full range
the main verb of the sentence containing 'claim is not make, any
is preposterous.
Myron's
b. We are discussing their. claim that
etc.
But after the verb make, and only after it, the
demonstrate.
must refer back to the subject of the modal verb -- indicate clearly
that sentential nouns like claim. hooe, etc. which occur in these
in complement sentences after make the claim, have hopes, etc. and
the fact that that can be deleted there could be handled by ordering
Modalization.
went mad.
That Deletion
Modalization
it.---H>Passive
by Jack.
148
constructions must be derived from some other source than the sentential
At any rate, I will not settle for merely an ad hoc rider on (4.20)
about is sick.
questioned: the fact that the sentences of (4.15) and (4.16) are
propose is that the re' zion between the sentences of (4.3) must be
much more complex than has hitherto been suspected. I suspect that
(4.3b) is nearer to being basic than (4.3a) is, and that in any case,
sentence", to use their term. They do not state how this restriction
clear from
is to be expressed foimally, but their meaning will be
days.
NP's which does not dominate the other. Since this is not true of
150
2
himi
?himself l
l
cannot go down into relative clauses, and I would not know how to
them, but not into clauses like the one shown in (4.63).
me
(4.63) I know a man who hates
myself
must depend in some way on this meta-rule. That is, one could assume
not the first, so the two NP's are not in the same simplex sentence.
VP
NP NP
I
read him NP
Art N NP
a statement
NP
about him
3.1.3, when the Relative Clause Reduction Rule deletes which was in
(3.6), thus bringing it about that the two occurrences of he (him) are
- d a or
- --,
or
0
417. ;
ood
at.,
- .
;A.
-7 ....or
...*.
--
"
...CT.
.
-
,
ow,
-.
T
-do.
L.
. /
.
no
with several facts which were first pointed out in two careful
are possessives, they do not occur (in most dialects). With the
without reflexives.
about himself.
Clearly, no principle like (3.6) can account for the facts in (4.65)
153
some of them are allowed in sentences like (4:65a) and possibly (4.65c).
(4.67) a. You are too flip with people who are jealous
of you.
you (*yourself).
watching me.
(*myself) .
Reflexivization
for the same reason that (4.5) cannot adequately account for the
the fact that reflexives can occur after about in (4.62 -) suggests
etching, sketch
picture
Warshawsky points out that the verbs associated with the nouns of
Further, she notes that certain of these verbs can occur only with
{painted
{ Michael the duck
(4 .74) sketched
*Michael's photograph
drew I
%.
pond.
but that others could have either human subjects or picture noun
subjects.
Michael
report
statement
description iltold of the conflict
(4.75) Michael's story described the country
article stated that we were at fault
book
?picture
I.
that any abstract noun can serve as subject of these verbs -- only
Marilyn's arrival 11
stated that we were at fault
,etc.
and with respect to the curious selectional facts pointed .out in (4.75)
157
Warshawsky sug,:ests that verbs may be basic for picture nouns, and
detailed analysis along these lines, little more can be. said
about it at present.
r-
would suggest that NP like a key to this door and a road into the
cavern should not be derived from ?a key which is to this door and
fall within the scope of (4.20), are in fact much more complex than
in footnote 8 and4.1.5.
table and?
some sofa?
The impossibility of questioning the circled NP nodes in diagram
principle,
(4.79)
but this principle does not prevent the circled NP nodes in diagrams
(4.80)
He_ nr
(4.81)
S and
VP
/4
Dolished her trombone
But all of the circled nodes must somehow be restricted from being
madrigals is warped.
fellow.
(4.83) NP
NP
meta-theory:
(4.85)
and
or
.
A A ....
{
162
with respect to the conjuncts, there are many reasons for believing
Floyd loafed.
(4.87)
1,!..PIORMIOPPTPPRVIITITRMRPOPWPWWIrfP.Prr..-,..Fgrrewns.frogro..-.
163
(4.86)
Irma washed the dishes and Sally dried and Floyd loafed 1
One'syntactic reason is that if a conjoined sentence like
always goes with the second sentence, as in (4.90a), never with the
first, as in (4.90b).
inserted into one conjunct (this is the case with - que 'and' in
Latin, and with the word aber 'but' in German), these enclitics
are always associated with the following conjunct, never with the
preceding one. Thus (4.91) may be converted into (4.92a), but not
into (4.92b).
gehen.
gehen.
there are very general theoretical grounds for arguing that the string
watermelon.
love watermelon.
165
watermelon,
structure of (4.86) must be that given in (4.88). But how does this
(and,
(4.96) S S , where n > 2
or
(4.97)
an
VP NP VP VP
IP 111.3
Irma NP Sally V NP Floyd, V
(4.98)
and
and
Irma washed the dishes Sally dried something Floyd loaf
are NP, VP, or V. The rules for conjunction with or are similar
the case if the previously accepted analyses were adopted. That is,
4C /A 071 4n nA, mA ec
4%. .0%0
4-1-tn
.--r ..... nc IL RAI
...--e, 1.11p. Pn-Milnet-inng
interpret (4.87) semantically, and the fact that and, or, and see
expressed formally.
(2.18) and (2.19), while the second will exclude all the sentences
the morpheme and which must be derived from different sources than
the two major sources discussed in Lakoff and Peters (1966). For
la 3
168
whisky.
and bought.
the shirts.
hbtu.ease
111 eve:ytin - ) """
UW. MT)
4.4 the ryln4clev, is 'Int- T.P1ativi7Ab1e
as (4.104b) indicates.
excellent whisky.
which contains a purpose clause, and the fact that the ungrammaticality
shows.
shirts up.
whisky.
,.1r.rrrprovenvbe....
170
store to buy.
your granny.
The fact that the sentences of (4.108) and sentence (4.101a) are
grammatical might mean that (4.84) is simply wrong, but the facts
questions, relative clauses, etc. are formed, but only are converted
structure than the one (4.84) provides, and it therefore seems quite
in a quonset hut.
(4.110)
and
NP
works works
1
in skyscraper
..1r.r.0.71.11.1F,T,,,,
172
Uncle Sam.
nose.
coordinate structure even after appina. has applied, i.e., that the
Peters (op. cit.) argue that (4.112) should be derived from (4.113) by
173
CAnt'Arle.P, 13
check.
(4.113)
NP
and
NP VP
Pietro Sofia
/4 \
:bought a Ferrari from me
derived structure..
4.2.4.
not apply. These are rule schemata which move a constituent out of all
175
and then deletes the original nodes. Thus this rule converts (4.118),
(4.118)
everyone V
be Neves
pregnant
re
176
(4.119)
an pregnant
1
NP 'VP NP
1
ANP
believes it S
NAP VP
Sheila definitely is
these grapes.
177
grapes.
must also apply "across the board "; the relative clause in (4.122)
disjunction, as in (4.123),
(4.123)
will be executed
NP
students or
VP NP VP
may apply in some conjuncts but not in others (cf. (4.125b) and (4.125c)).
of he'll talk.
table off.
early to look for formal properties of rules which correlate with the
Extraaosition, and many others like them which could be cited, me-ely
179
Conjunction Reduction which was given above, that this rule moves
of Relative Clause Formation which was givenin (4.2) that this rule
must also move elements out of conjuncts. Under the normal interpreta-
symbolized by ' +' in the structural change of (4.2), when one term
rule in (4.126).
(4.126) Extraposition
X - [it Y
NP
OPT
1 2 3 4
1 2 0 4+3
NP VP
\NP
V
claimed
(4.128) It Deletion
X - [it - S] Y
NP
OBLIG
1 2 3 4
1 0 3 4
is not relevaim for my argument, and I have drawn two dotted lines
(4.129)
eggs 11.,
.11=10
S
%\
I
this rule would not delete the it in (4.129), and the ungrammatical
(4.130) X - it - S - Y
OBLIG
2 3 4
>
1 0 3 4
which ic; thc cLject of claim will 110 deleted, hicAr,_Auge it precedes
will result.
found of indicating that the sentence that Bob was a nut is somehow
but that this is not the case with respect to the sentence and I think
neighbor.
183
only prevents constituents from being moved, it must be the case that
would not be moved by (4.2), and thus the constraint would not
17
be in effect. But if (4.2) is reformulated as in (4.135), the
,- NP
s
X - NP Yi
S NP
Z
-NP
OBLIG
1 2 3 4 5 6 >
1 2 4# [3 0 5] 6
Condition: 2 v: 4
the sequence of terms enclosed in the brackets, in this case, the node
18
S. Thus (4.135) cony .7ts (4.136a) into (4.136b) .
184
(4.136) a. NP
/
the 'oily:
,
NP
crn
V4
I V
/',ZN NP
b. NP
NP
t'he 1.2sLy. NP
NP
"\\VP
I V
saw
And since (4.84) would prevent the circled NP node in (4.137) from
(4.137) NP
the bob VP
and I have proposed. Both rules would have the effect of moving
and possibly
elements contained in conjuncts out of those conjuncts,
it is this formal property that the fact that they are both across-
(4.138) a. When did you get back and what did you
bring me?
got sick.
of. Support for such a proposal comes 7rom the fact that it is not
allowed.
word nani 'what' and add the question, morpheme ka to the end of the
sentence, as in (4.143)
cat sleeping is
41
188
mita ka (to)
(4,145) * Zyoozyi wa rani o mite neko
mi
ga nete iru.
'What did George see and what did the cat eat?'
the problem in universal grammar of ensuring that only the "right kinds"
this claim. Thus it seems that even questions like those in (4.147),
which contain more than one WH-word but presumably have no history of
189
would?
this sentiment.
The fact that sentences like (4.139b) and (4.152) are ungrammatical
Jack left
. a ,
"I+ -
190
which has not applied to all conjuncts, because the only rule in
the subject Ou. It therefore seems that only some deep structure
questions turns out to be, my basic point remains. valid: there are
it away.
when relative clauses are formed from the sentences in (4.154), both
the NP's blintzes, that contract and the curtain themselves and
some loopholes.
Priscilla.
of art.
importance for this study, since I ca101ot even propose a rule which
6
will generate less questionable examples, such as (4.155) and (4.156e).
above is the fact that not only does it seem possible to relativize
---"""."4"..."ne"rynnrwrn......7-..7.-
193
(4.159) shows.
wallpaper.
forgery.
pattern.
(cf. (4.160)):
crspo InnphniA.q,
Priscilla.
that the rule of pronoun deletion which transforms (4.161) into (4.155)
explanation does not yet have much force, for I have no idea what
upon, nor how to state the rule, but perhaps it is at least a correct
structure may not be. The statement of the constraint in (4.84) was
theory of grammar.
successfully account for the evidence for the A-over-A principle which
will provide for the generation of all the relative clauses in the
convenience.
197
(4.162)
N1)
/IN
the government
1
rescr es NP
the heisia,
'the lettering,
"the covers
of. IILL929TU.
,..4.7,7,...-..1.779.,171.74M+IRTF7717...1=
d'47+-27
198
should be abolished.
such a way that the new rule would derive either (4.163a) or (4.163b)
0 - NP
(4.164) W NP - X - Y]S i Z
s NP
NP [NPNP P NP2NP
OBLIG
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 2[45]10 0 0 61 7
Condition: 2 m 5
199
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 2[4 5]#[3 0 0 6] 7
Condition: 2 as 5
and deriving the clause in (4.163d) would entail adding a fourth line
theory is to make the claim that there are other cases, unrelated
universal convention.
containing many NP nodes, which is singled out from all other nodes
operating on some NP singled out in some such way may instead operate
for the adioining to the front of the sentence of the specified NP7,
the reports, or NP6, of the reports, or NP5, the covers of the reports,
noun phrases which start with prepositions from being relativized and
questioned when these directly follow the NP they modify. Thus (4.168)
of (4.166).
(4.170)
NP
watched
Bill 'the ha
of (4.171)7
vain.
(4.173)
VP
(4.174) shows,
once again, (4.166) would allow the preposing of the boxed node
between two occurrences of the node NP, only the lower one can
(4.177)
ich
VP anciefanc,e1
NP
i2 zu versuchen
NP
en hund zu rrnaen O
PmerrITWIM.prow
205
-1-J-- // 1'70\
UnUeL3.y.i.u6 vt J../Uvit
1
the rule of Relative Clause Formation must produce all three of the
discussed.
A
A 4.3.2.0. The convention stated in (4.180) stipulates that any NP
one, but there are environments where the lower NP may not be moved,
and only some higher one can, consonant with the conditions imposed in
24
(4.180). In other words, pied piping is obligatory in some contexts.
in §§ 4.3.2.1 -
4.3.2.1. For English, and for many other languages, the following
constraint, which has the effect_ .of _making pied piping obligatory
by a transformational rule.
(4.184a)
208
(4.183)
NP VP
we NP
elected NP president
2
employer
the N duardian rs
been moved filma this branch. Since the Left Branch Condition
209
(4.185) Topicalization
X - NP Y
OPT
1 2 3 ------->
21/(1 0 3]
vvr,:::104 'tart r
president.
president.
which performs almost the same operation as. (4.185), except that it
NP1 over president (cf. (4.188a)),25 but neither NP2 nor NP3
demonstrates.
employer. N
b. * We elected employer president the boy's
guardian's. 1
c. * We elected guardian's employer president
the boy.
of the sentence alone -- pied piping must apply to carry NI', with
elect president?.
.11 I -14*
Do waxn Doy
il
_
gudEu.t.du we
employer president?
-employer president?
and (4.191h).
from an underlying NP, and the adjective sane and the adverb
which questions are formed. Note also that if the degree adverb
(4.194)
Sheila
married NP NP
2
R
a man
'
for (4.181) will not permit either NP3 or NP2 to be moved out
of NP .
1
One other set of facts deserves mention in connection with
II. Inc\
ve..4.7a, a. aueu DULL/L=LL 6eLLu:).L.J. liesh.Qu.a.u/L6=LL.
(4.185) to' derive (4.195b) from the structure which underlies (4.195a),
like sehr. If this reordering rule adjoins the adverbs which are
rule precedes the rule of T( calization, the fact that fast can be
214
that
topicalized with or without hUbsch (cf. (4.198)), bute,sehr cannot be
Branch Condition.
point in derivations, but the analysis sketched here has the virtue
as far as I can see. However, since I have not made a detailed study
grammar.
special cases of the Left Branch Condition, which will block the
EP ]NP'
pointed out that it is just with the class of nouns that cannot be
creepy.
does not obtain for English, the modified version shown in (4.206)
does:
(4.200), and (4.206) - are all cases where the optionality which is
reorder, but the above three constraints limit this freedom: they
the next section, I will discuss two constraints which have the
opposite effect.
movable, the preposition may not be lamed with it. Thus though
are not.
other verbs which seem to be of exactly the same syntactic type for
218
to speak out.
of, make light of, get hold of, etc. Normally, in my speech at
least, the preposition must be left behind for most of these idioms --
to keep us in suspense.
light of?
to keep us in suspense.
made light?
which the preposition seems to be movable, just ad was the case with
R
219
varnr4on.
fantastically corrupt.
(4.212) are the exception, rather than the rule, so presumably some
(4.208)), an adjective (as in make light of, make sure of, etc.), a
verb (as in make do with, let fly at, let go of, lathold of, yet rid of
(if rid should be analyzed as a verb here)), lay claim to, hold sway over,
siege to,
Pay heed to, etc.), a noun (as in get wind of, set fire to,. lay
make use of, lose track of, tekeshatot, take umbrae:7e at, etc.), or
possibly a noun phrase (e.g., ,get the droacal, make no bones about,
220
to me, that the difference between (4.211) and (4.212) may correlate
That is, in many cases, verbs like those in (4.212), where the
preposition may be moved, allow either the first element after the
passive.
skirts.
to.
subject to (4.213), have double passives. But the idioms in (" .%0),
cality of (4.211), have only one passive, as can be seen f2-011 the
a
221
manuscripts.
and the class of idioms whose prepositions' are not subject to (4.213)
lemma.
to Sikolsky.
the station.
proved to be innocent.
222
. ."-
I suspect that intensive research into this .problem would yield rich
I
,
4
...-T.,-
i
223
ungrammatical.
must be stated:
dominated by VP.
it must be blocked.
the left, nor the rule of Comnlex NP Shift, which moves them to
preposed, as it is in (4.226c)
Kasten] ] schmeissen.
NP Np
box throw.
this box.'
in schmeissen?
into throw?
I
225
%in}, cni-min4ccestl? 11
book throw
the book?'
although the English rule is not so restricted as the German one. Since
I have not studied the conditions under which such sentences as (4.227b)
only move the larger NP, in diesen Kasten (cf. (4.228)). If the
226
in diescn Kasten,
diesen Kasten.
the left.
to the left, they may not be if it is moved to the right. The rule
yesterday.
yesterday.
yester:ay.
my friends.
my friends.
227
border.
suspect, however, that (4.213) does not have to be modified and that
some other rule than Complex NP' Shift is being used in the generation
28
positioned between any major constituents of a clause. Note
the commas are removed, but that no commas are necessary in such
cookie jar.
the rule which converts (4.118) into (4.119). Since the adjective
(4.234)
a nc1S
NP VP.
am confident I NP
I-1
NP ,depends 4
i.
"of
into (4,231) which weakens it so that it does not affect the operation
for they are contained in the boxed NP nodes, which start with
_
230
was on a right branch, but the rule will also work on constituents
is sentence (4.237).
(4.236)
an
VP
he University s. students
the University
(4.238)
an
Condition, (4.181), will prevent the boxed NP's in (4.238) from being
raised, because each is on the left branch of a larger 1114. These facts
on pied pipirig are aot in effect for the rule of Conjunction Reduction,
Conjunction Reduction.
(4.240)
vp
P kisstlE
233
b.
grandmother
aunt's
234
-1 /A ni.,3-N .1-,
A4GXe-,..-
u4 &cu.. ucuwell. A.rie traTiMat.A.Ccu. v.1.4.1J4, and cam. ungrammarLed.i.
(4.243b).
..
NP, when it moves, this larger NP will pied pipe with it, as (4.181)
requires.
(4.244) O
grandmother
NP
Tom's aunt's
Since the circled NP in this tree does not occur in all conjuncts,
the boxed NP node in (4.244) must pied pipe, for the NP being
Constraint, (4.84). And since there f.s a clause in the Pied Piping
of (4.244) will not pied pipe either. Thus the circled NP node is
the way (4.84) and (4.181) have been stated prevent any NP node
236
constructs.
at present.
cf. (4.248).
grammars the rule of Scramblins. appears, that the Left Branch Condition
when a language will exhibit the Left Branch Condition and when not.
that exhibits them. But must each such condition be stated on each
set of five rules that they are all subject to (4.181).. I am making
'and (4.231). For French, Italian and German, it will contain (4.181) ,
which are introduced by etta 'that'. That is, while such sentences
wore?
koskaan kayttanyt?
ever used.
other languages.
the need for a convention of some sort. Rather than devise some
made use of to :candle these facts) I have chosen the convention stated
of cases where pied piping is obligatory and suggested that the theory
Structure Constraint.
241
(4.250c).
(4.251) shows.
battleax.
II nen%
Vto4.04) Of which cars were Che Luods damaged by
the explosion?
(4.253)
into account.
21.3
-^",4
4W.IV4U %di 4.1.44Also P
44
iL 41.0111 AIOUG
immediately dominated by S.
because there are languages whose rules are not subject to it. In
shows.
ga akiraka da.
obvious is
(4.256) S
NP
,
L____ \\
N SA akiraka da
NP koto
kabutte ita
Mary sono
1
boosi
a
245
English.
the nurse.
1
246
(4.259)
If .
strange to
will not be able to account for the clear difference in status between
two sentences:
piano.
loudly.
32
Lees gives a number of arguments which show these to be different.
(4.262)
NP
.'/
disliked NP NP
NP
A
P
of the piano
(4.263)
V N."?
playing ar.....t.ass 1
249
the former does not, can be seen from the difference in relativizability
when the Relative Clause Formation Rule applies, pied piping can be
result.
between the two NP nodes, and under these conditions, pied piping
250
everyone crazy.
everyone crazy.
of (4.266b) dominates the node S, pied piping cannot take place. But
grammar, the top line of (4.2673) will not be excluded. Note that
251
S is a gerund.
you?
that both (4.268), the revised version of (3.27), and the Sentential
(4.260a) and (4.260b), aad in the second, between (4.267a) and (4.267b).
clauses as objects but for which the rule which normally can optionally
(4.271) a. * Which hat did Mike quip that she never wore?
hat?
box, like the Finnish one, contains the constraint that no element
verbs like believe do not come to be headed by*that until after all
verbs like quip are prefixed by that at a very early stage in derivations.
This then raises the possibility that the condition that no element be
(op. cit.) that this condition is only a subcase of a far more general
condition, (4.272).
normal to me. And the third objection is that elements of clauses with
be'
Poss - Ina or for - to complementizers can be relativized, as can
from the fact that Reflexivization cannot "go down into" them (cf.
from *he fact that elements of these clauses can undergo "backwards"
33
pronominalization (cf. (4.275)) ,
cages with.
parakeets.
I
255
the theory of language and those grammars in which the latter constraint
and I am sure that the few conditions I have discussed are not only
wrong in detail, but in many major ways. Not only must further work,
represented.
1
widpc.4.1.,L ti
FOOTNOTES 256
Oa,
257
But such niceties are not at issue here (4.25) will serve for
she found
in a wide variety of languages that she conducted,
the left.
258
NP S or by the rule NP S
259
or
B 'A A
But the stress rules will only work properly if the formative
of the stress rules of English, cf. Halle and Chomsky (to appear)).
kind of adjunction.
with it.
"S.2."%iit"
261
the NP the boy who I saw, because many details of the correct
WH-questions, e.g.,
bring me?
I am sure I say such sentences often, but most of them seem some-
would force this more general version, I will propose the weaker,
one of (4.166).
21. The verb habe shave' has been moved to the eud of the 'relative
dependent clauses:
will have been pruned by the time the rule of Relative Clause
verbs and those with non- finite main verbs in the revised
version of (4.166).
reality of (4.180).
following the original Pied Piper was obligatory for all the
children of the town except one, who was lame, so that the
..7,66Y&a
4.1q^e.ca
ftsavory fleten1.41.%15A
YVVYf ... 1%GaleM1
YYYYY.
While the point they make is valid, I have chosen to disregard its
25. The fact that NP does not dominate So and that (4,188a) is
1
Of this rule.
revised. It is abtindoned entirely in (5.57), the final statement
the how in (4.190a) does not replace to what extent, but rather
to (4.191b).
1_ .....14.7,m'ne9N
place
265
0"o(1
efaWo
it ,, Aisu/
a-1...o. /A 1'27% 40 no nr,rnmat-tnnl unlAag ConiunetiOn
30. Later rules will convert (4.242b) into the boy's uncle and
aunt's grandmother.
:2. Cf. Lees (1960), pp. 65.67. I will follow his terminology in
'gerund nominal.
and k3 beim.
267
Chapter 5
which could be handled with command but not with bounding, there
were also facts for which the opposite was the case. Recently,
.....,...7....11.....w ,
268
I'will show how all these facts can be accounted for with command,
5.1. 222.12.12,aa
I
J.A.04.41,
sentence.
269
........... .......... .M.
(5.1)
13ke girls
(5.2)
1
.42 2 ears
,
for
VP
like girls
270
NP
we
expect N
it
H a La to VP
like gi is
NP VP
expect . for
VP
.....
....,..
like girls
271
shown in (5.6)
(5.6)
NP VP
VP 12141IEIL2111:Laal
it appears to be true
an output.
- .
272
(5.7)
VP
.1.
it appears,
true
<5.9)
NP
it appears, for
44, .0WWW
'be true
of the intuitive structure of (5.5), for it not only makes the claim
claims strike me as being the exact opposites of the truth about the
v....Y.
274
(5.10)
NP
be true
made a last-cyclic rule, but this is not the only means of arriving
at the correct derived structure for sentences like (5.5). Noam Chomsky
sentences as (5.11),
(5.11) This is the dog that chased the cat that caught
(5.12)
NP S
NP S
equal size precede each occurrence of that, unless some rule were
and he suggests thatthe same rule which raises the nested sentences
rule.
(5.14)
NP VP
Ivan
'figure out
I
278
but not. when the one in the subject of (5.15b) was. I believe the
embedded sentences -- that is, that there are two passes made
open question, then Particle Movement could not apply to it, and
to impose the condition upon (3.9) that it not operate in any sentence
!..V.,
279
135), contexts from higher sententuts than the ore being processed cannot
Mbvealent would have to be allowed 0 apply freely, and that some ad hoc
undesirable.
with a preposition.. _Thus the particle ....razart may not be moved over
It is necessary to claim that idioms like do away with, sit in on, etc.,
verb followed by two prepositions and a noun phrase, for it is the case
(e.g. along, hit, on, in, off, 211., etc., as opposed to at, among, for, etc.)
ungrammatical (5.18)?
(5.17)
was obvious
lying.
obvious.
(5.18).
the A-over-A principle. But since the facts given in § 2.1 show
(2.7) to produce (2.8), but not (2.9), all of which I reproduce here
for convenience©
282
(2.7)
VP
was 'given,
VP
whose head noun is the pronoun it cannot be'moved out of these clauses,
principle which was strong enough to exclude (5.18), but weak enough
(5.20)
N1
i
is possible O
1///
it NP
284 .
obvious that Fxtraposition from NP must also be; for it, like
How can this sentence be blocked? Even if it were assumed that the
two rules of extraposition were the same, and could be collapsed into,
below), the A-over-A principle could not be invoked to. block (5.21).
other has been. Thus if neither has been, (5.22a) results; if only S2
has been, (5.22b) results; if only S3 has been, (5.22c) results; and
intervene between them. That is, the rules must be ordered as in (5.23).
2. Extraposition (4.126)
3. (question (4.1)
4. 1trai
postionfrojLE)NP(1.10)
kapstion, for if S2 has not been moved out of NP1 to the end of
(5.26)
VP
N is possible that NP
which packages
and copula are inverted, the resulting structure is (5.27), not the
I
288
(5.27)
eishPA,shr Is it V that NP O
ages
(5.28)
VP
which aackages is
a large constituent break after the particle 12. It might appear that
(5.30)
didn't pick NP
(5.30)? If some constraint can be stated on this rule which has the
4rt 4,11
enA of
G.11 . W1 wa.s.y 0.11.1VW.1.446 4.4AG Gebt.A.401,WOIA griiaMOG myvv
the first sentence up, then the rule could apply to (5.30) to produce
(5.31)
that the most normal version of this sentence would be (5.33), not
(5.29).
tomorrow.
has not been extraposed away from its head NP, which packages,
is possible
it that
NP
clause, as in (5.36).
recognize him?
the fact that the preferred order in the non-embedded case, i.e.,
of (5.37) shows.
raining?
(5.40)
a girl came in NP
who
this coat
(5.41) * The coat whidh a girl came in who had worn was
torn.
295
why this should be so: what (5.42) says, in effect, is that elements
of complex noun phrases, which are prohibited from being moved before
the rule of Extraposition from NP has applied are also prohibited after
this rule has applied. In other words, (5.42) must duplicate the
evidence that this rule is not cyclic, since it must follow Particle.
1. Extraposition is last-cyclic.
298
theory of grammar.
5.1.2.
first sentence above the elements being operated on. I will refer to
as ranging over all nodes of the tree which are below the first
double line above the nodes Of (5.43) which could be affected by the
adjoined to the largest part of the tree consistent with this convention.
That is, the S will move to the right,up to the first double line.
any combination of these, (5.43) will become one of the eight sentences
10
of (5.44).
(5.43)
is not true
not true.
was obvious.
not true.
guards.
true.
obvious.
not true.
throw a fit.
301.
(5.46) Extraposition of PP
X - NP]Np - Y
OPT
1 2 3 -
1 0 3+2
of this article.
(5.48)
NI' *vP
,,'///(
it for NP
a review NP
of this article
(5.49)
a review
seems NP
77'
to have come out yesterday
/
P
of this article
(5.50)
NP NP
a review
previous structures, it seems unlikely that the rule which converts (5.12)
304
home.
gets home.
gets home?
Extraposition of PP is last-cyclic.
vP
11 is catastrop ic
it that NP VP
a review
of this article
article is catastrophic.
of this article.
does not begin with a preposition. The removal of the first condition
will mean that (5.56b), which results from the application of the rule
306
NP Shift.
(5.57) NP Shift
X - NP - Y
OPT
1 2 3
1 0 3+2
Condition 2: BLOCKS if 3 = X
1 + [ +Adj,i + X2 2
g# [P NP)NP.
Shift and Extra position of PP are the same rule is not of great
true no matter how many rules (5.57) must be broken down into
(5.58) Any rule whose structural index is of the form
upward bounded.
unless the following facts can be explained in some other way than
midnight.
reading.
(5.60)
promised
that NP
*a.
308
(5.61)
NP
NP around midnight
pis d 1
tha
he would be there
there.
by a consideration of_(5.63).
tense verb 22.2119122.d. Now note that the rule of Adverb Preposing, which
converts (5.59) into (5.62), cannot convert (5.63) into (5.64), for
The adverb tomorrow can be proposed, but only to the front of the
eirml,c,AAc.A #4,^
...so. .c.44
/C 401
vreva/flo
there.
X- f+Adverbi - 'Y
OPT>
1 2 3
2 + 1 0 3
rule, the only way to prevent the adverb around midnight from
when tae preposed adverbs have heavy stress. Sentence (5.62) becomes
as (5.69) show.
life.
syntactic minimal pair here: while all rules which adjoin elements
33.1
the it, the copula and the relative pronoun in these sentences
topicalized sentences.
would be there.
in his life.
the transformational cycle, nor the AoverA principle, nor any of the
A 6. it, 3
(Klima (1964)).
a. X - (+ Affective] Indeterminate] --
1- 2 - 3 - 4 - 5
1- 2 - 3 - 4 -1 - 5
Indef site
b. X - Indeterminate] Y (+ Affective]
1-
1 2 4 - 5
Indeterminate 3
refers to as
certain contexts, and certain lexical items which Klima
quantifiers like some, to indefinite ones like ay: Klima uses the
alone?
to kill.
kill.
314
44 16.&41.4.V. 1J
^
&4V 64GgcsiVG .1.44 1.4iG
Jw J.wAlwwdb.J...w we IMUw
ALJA4.1.0211.iVG Vd. 11141G a.w.:41.
that some's can be converted into any's indefinitely far away from
can take place in questions, and (5.73d) shows why rule (5.71) must
well as forwards, and also that the adjectives certain and odd must
differ in their marking for the frature [Affective]: the first must
place in the same clause as the one in which, the (+Affective] element
with, which I will discuss in' §-5.2.2 below, but this notion is not
the head noun the claim appears. The fact that (5.71) will neither go
315
pleased somebody.
laughed.
pleased anybody.
laughed.
(5.76).
(J.76) a.
NP
Tom NP
he wasn't sick
Amiiip.IMIN11100.0.111111
316
(5.76) b.
VP
(5.76) c.
bounded, and is not permitted to cross the first double line up from
the (+Affective] source. In other words, while rule (5.71) can effect
changes indefinitely far down the tree from the element that causes the
will be affected.
b. Al [ A21
J
(5.79a) and (5.79b), which are of exactly the same syntactiz type as
318
like (5.71) are allowed to apply to them, .while the former two cause
pleased Sami.
pleased himi.
5.1.3.2.
5.1.3.2.1. As a second example of an upward bounded feature-changing
rule, let us consider facts from Finnish which are closely related to
sentences are unusual and would only be used to convey some such
(5.82) To in kirjaa.
far down the tree from the negative morpheme. (5.84) shows a simple
up in detail here, reveals that the Finnish rule, unlike the English rule,
I 1 In
320
allt
approximation, as in (5.85).
- 2 -3- 4 -5
I. - 2 -3- [ 4 I -- 5
+parti
make it upward bounded. That this is necessary can be seen from the
tuomaan'to bring' in the partitive case, except with the unuzual sense
- -
321
(5.87)
_NP
poika NP
.1.21ca rei V
L+Neg.I 0.
jensit
and since the negative morpheme ei is to the left of and below the
(5.89)
b. ja etovo ne sdelal
I will not deal with here. (5.91) .s one example of such a change.
eto sdelat1
(5.91) ja ne xocu
etovo
with the verbs of the sentences separating the negative element from
the accusative noun phrase wh:,,ch the rule is to operate on. For
example, the verb xotet !want' allows the negative to affect noun
phrases in Its complement, while the verb nacat. 'begin' does not.
The class of verbs like xo,_ tet, appears to be small, and it may not
of (5.93) and (5.94) would not constitute proof that (5.92) must
in support of (5.77).
324
X- [.+Negi Y [+acc] - Z
1- 2 - 3 - 4 - 5
1- 2 3 I 4 -5
L--genj
as term 3, then facts which parallel those of (5.86) and (5.88) can
tree -- (5.92) must be upward bounded. And for the same reasons that
(5.95)
eto (acc.) in the second clause will be prevented from being converted
b. oni uvazajetsebjai
17
ljevoi
(5.97) a. on. sostavil menja uvazat,
i::::jai
b. 'He forced me to respect
himself
(5.98) Reflexivization
X - NP - Y - NP - =
1 2 3 4 5
1 2 3 4 1 5
L+Refl-.1
Condition: 2 = 4
as being upward bounded. That this is necessary can be seen from the
me to respect him
him.'
v
b. * zenscvv ina kotoruju on ljubil sostavila
i
menja uvaIat, sebjai.
and can mean either 'The woman who he loved forced me to respect her',
the fact that (5.98) is upward bounded will prevent this undesired
(5.100)
NP////7
V V71
Y
ZengLna S sostavila NP
kotoraia NP
f1/4 VP uvazvat
.
i2Y21
.oni ljubq
328
Once again, (5.101b) has a meaning, but not the same meaning that
(5.101a) has. It means 'He loves the woman, and I respect myself.'
(5.102)
upward bounded.
While (5.103b) can mean 'He knows that she loves herself',
in (5.105), demonstrates:
(5.105)
loyooki de aru
tt
330
rule of Reflexivization can be stated the same way the Russian rule
was. And, just as the Russian rule is, the Japanese rule must be
upward bounded. This can be seen from the fact that (5.106a), whose
(5.107)
5) to iu koto wa
.-
*-
f
331.
the left of and below a double line, as seen from the boxed NP,
upward bounding will prevent rule (5.98) from converting this structure
---
into (5.106b) .
[+acci y.
V x -Pro_i
1 2 3 4
1 2 3 1 4
accounts for the fact that in sentences whose subjects have been
derivation still has a subject mint, 'I', the direct objects of the
verbs zyyte 'to ask' and tuomaan 'to bring' appear in the accusative
case.
kirjan.
become (5.110b) .
332
That (5.108) must be upward bounded can be seen from the fact that
19
(5.11a), whose structure is that shown in (5.112), must be converted
lehden.
'Bring the book (nom.), and I'll bring the paper (acc.
(5.112)
VP NP
V NP mina
t U0 'tuon lehden
So".4.011Metasra.
333
support of (5.77) is the rule which changes tense, ill some contexts
the sentence. Thus while both is and was are possible in (5.113),
20
only was is in (5.114) .
to me to assume that the rule which effects the change of tense must
a. X -144/ Y HAT] Z
L aTensei
1 2 3 4 5
1 2
3 [aT:nse]
4-11
b. X - PV] Y aTensej
2 3 4
1 [ 2 j 3 6 5
aTens
.,&
11:
That this, rule is far too strong can be seen from the
fact that it would only allow the version of (5.113) ia which is appears
(5.115) effects is much too simple-minded a change, and that the correct
that (5.115) must be upward bounded, so that it will allow the generation
all the tenses in (5.117) agree with believed (or with one of the other
verbs in (5.117)), thus making the incorrect claim chat sentences cannot
ical.
rules. In this section I will discuss three cases which suggest that
, .
335
should now be raised is the following one: should both this notion
characterize the difference between the English and the Japanese rules
term is chosen, then the fact that the restrictions on the English
rule are in part universal cannot be captured. For the fact that
rule, The only way to express the fact that the English rule is
sentence.
So for the purposes of the present discussion, I will assume that the
bounded.
<<
337
above. There I pointed out that clitics must be moved so that they
the path of the dotted arrow, but only that of the solid arrow.
(5.119)
NP VP
`1
///\\
NP VP
EP,
--^
338
cries out for explanation: all downward bounded rules are upward
bounded, but the converse is not true. That is, while there are
rules whose scope extends indefinitely far down the tree from the
no rules whose scope extends indefinitely far up the tree, but not
5.2. Command
5.2.1.
I will show that Langacker's notion of command can account for all the
above A.
339
and N.
ai a a- a - , - I. J:._
A.CD43.1A06.Vi4 VA UpW4A04 UVUALU..0
r_ -
A.Vi.
- a al.. a -a _2. & a a
&AUG V6liCir DAA AGAUUMG-41a46..a6
al a
.- -r 1"-^1%.-, zvt,
343.
not only between one node and another, but may hold between one node
same way the conditions would. And it is evident that the operation
command each other. This condition makes it impossible for the elements
S nodes must be the same. That is, two nodes which command each
bounding. Before showing that the former theory is stronger than the
p. 297):
That this relation is stronger than command can be seen from (5.121),
this condition is too strong can be seen from (5.125a), which (5.71)
int- that contains the feature Affective] and triggers the change.
344
But the structure which Klima would assign to (5.125) (cf., e.g.,
UMW
(5.126)
NP Pre. cate
Aux
Prs
fective] possible
and in this structure, the circled node geg, which carries the feature
one structure for which Klima's notion produces the wrong results, and
be chosen even if only the facts connected with rule (5.71) are taken
into consideration.
0
345
is too strong.
structure of (5.129a).
(5.128)
I NP
talked
Winston
(5.129) a. * I talked to Winstoni about i
him
(5.131)
NP
41 obvious
that the sun is'out 4-Pasti
was
.
1
347
where the tensed yell) was is not in construction with the verb is
25
in the sentential subject, the generalization in (5.127) would not
To say that two nodes command each other is to say that they are elements
of the same simplex sentence, but to say that they are in construction
they do not show that the latter notion cannot supplement the former
5.2.3.
a
AV/
348
underlying (5.133b).
in such away that the difference between his arm in the first clause
not the case that all differences between pronouns can be disregarded:
(5.134) a. John scratched his arm and the boy whc. knew
.
349
the circled NP's John and Mary command the circled pronouns his and
his arm
his, but the boxed NP Mary does not command its pronoun her, so
(5.137)
scratched
the boxed NP Lam. does not command its boxed pronoun, her.
(5.139)
but N' VP
didn't worry NP
N_
thelia who
will appear in the theory of grammar. And since (5.135) makes crucial
grammar, and not the notion of bounding. For notice that bout_ing,.
and that here some static relation is necessary, in order for the
5.2.3.2. It is for the same reason that command, but. not bounding,
my friends were.
he wasn't.
he would be.
b. ....than Sally expected Joan tobelieve
clauses, they will command only the other elements of these clauses.
And the not of (5.142c) is one clause lower than the compared adjective,
facts about identity discussed above, and the rules which Langacker
5.3. Pronominalization
is unbounded, the statements of rules for which also make crucial use
30
of variables -- pronominalization. In § 5.3.1, I will discuss
they obey the same constraint which the rule that introduces the
that they obey no other constraint thus far discussed, and discuss
and will not be dealt with here. For instance, the rules which convert
knows it.
respectively.
Harry tomatoes.
ungrammatical (5.145b).
A
356
(5.149) a.
v.
N?
who we watched
the prize
/
NP
which
However, this rule must not be stated in a way that ',lakes crucial tse
(5.147b).
(5.148c)
b.
V T%
which [ NP
-1.Prol_
tc'..- wanted
was shown with reference to the sentences in (5.80), and they will
below).
cLutle.feelsgood,nra.%.7ill go.
stated in (5.153).
by it.
359 .
These conditions are almost identical, but not quite. To see this,
consider the two sentences of (5.154) (these are the sentences numbered
asked me to.
asked me to.
(5.155) :
(5.155)
P;DP
NP PD.P
%mallows.*
Harveyi Harvey
(5.154a) is that it contains two clauses, the main clause being I gave
the book to Harvey, and the subordinate clause being because he asked
me to. Such a parsing would yield some structure like that shown in
(5.156).
(5.156)
(5.154a) occurs after the pronoun I, and that I gave the book to Harvey
conditions obtain.
361
people's desires..
104.
I might want 414.U6.1,,w40
ig.7n1 ga mnrA nearly basic than the one underlying (5.157b), but
(5.158)
it t at I might want to e e.
because he is insensitive to other
people's desires
- a
362
for here, the extraposed clause does not move over a VP.
(5.160).
(5.160)
The clause to be extraposed, S2, must command any string over which
Langacker (op. cit.) pp. 16-18), which can be accounted for with the
0
5.3.3.
which produce paradigms like the one in (5.146). It may turn out that
the same rule, but I will not attempt such a proof here. I will merely
show that they are similar to the rule which produces l.finite
pronoun one does not. That this rule is subs ct to (5.152) can be
had left.
came in.
came in.
365
left.
left.
1
came in.
in.
preparation a),
-..
366
(5.166)
NP
Webster
1
did
it
Webster V NP
touch a sword
S Deletion.
done it.
a sword.
it.
a sword.
under identity, replacing them with the morpheme so. It may eventually .
so}
(5.168) a. Did the Mets win? If , I've lost
*it
$500,000.
368
done so.
a sword.
did so.
a sword.
sentences of (5,172)
can work on it
you work on it
(5.171) I'll work on it if
noone else has worked on it
am will be working on it
(I can
Iy do
(5.172) I'll work on it ie nou
oone else had
Sam will be too
a
369
Lakoff and Ross (in preparation a) (cf. also Ross (1967b)) , I will
thinks so too.
do so today?
will tomorrow.
MOMONaJMN.11. 'UMW*. Mir
370
going steady.
6...lockoicarefullybrushedoffhis.tongue.
constrain the variable-in this rule. That they also do not constrain
me to 4y to do it in a glider would be
hazardous.
a
371
the bathrooms.
but the examples given here should provide a sound enough basis.for
this generalization.
Finnish, and in Ijo and a, two languages of West Africa, this seems
372
which have the form of (5.148) are constrained by (5.152); all rules in
of, a variable term at the right end of a structural index, and all
feature-changing rules, which have the form given in (5.78), are upward
I
373
Chapter 4.
374
Chapter 5
FOOTNOTES
until the 7.ast pass through the transfor-:tional cycle, where they
may precede rules which apply on each pass through the cycle, is
.
375
The fact that sentences (5.22a) and (5.22b) are of low accepta-
(5.28).
10. The fact that various sentences in (5.44) are rendered less than
12. For the purpose of stating this rule, I will make the dubious
all adverbs. Though trees (5.60) and (5.61) do not indicate the
15. David Perlmutter has called to my attention the fact that this
negative element (but cf. fn. 16)) and optional for elements of
/civet-
what were clauses in deep structure. He points out that this
A
restriction is shared by the Russian rule for reflexivization,
which must have the same restriction imposed on it. Th.i.s is the
of this example. For example, while both (5.93a) and (5.93b) are
the rOica
nl means 'whn never drank vodka'; with vodki (gen.): it
17. Since the reflexive pronoun sebia ii used for all persons, the
sentence on sostavil men a uvazat, sebja can also mean 'He forced
can be disregarded.
'That Mary was sick was obvious to me.' The fact that here zibun
can only refer to the first person suggests that in the deep
19. The reasons for not Pruning S1 in (5112) will be gone into in.
a-
378
rules to b2 both downward anu upward bounded. ILL this case, the
.22. There are many other complex conditions which have, to do with
David M. Perlmutter.
23. For a formal definition of the notion tree, cf. Zwicky and
Isard (1963) :
24. The problem of why rules of reflexivization should behave not like
below.
Aux + Tns (X) (Perf) (Prog), the notion in construction with will
I
- .
379
fact that the sentence That the fuzz wanted to question John
way that (5.138a) is. This means that the definition of linguistic
work.
28. All the following remarks apply equally well to the as-clause
. 30. By the phrase "crucial use of variables", I mean all rules whose
rules which make crucial use of variables are governed - that is,
32. In this rule, the letter A is a variable over node types, not
strings.
381
provisional. For arguments pro and con, see Lakoff (1967) and
37. For discussion of this construction, cf. Lakoff and Ross (1966),
as Wilfred, raised his hand and th,n that idiot, even tried to
Chapter 6
arises as to whether there are other rules than just the two studied in
rule will obey the constraints or not. This question has already been
rules, some apparently related, some not, showing that each is subject
the
place the copied constituent occupied before the operation of
nUell.%ev4v.r.
Iwt.c44.5J.4a6
A4c.nynn^A 4." 5 5.1.3 also obey the constraints. Th4s
and Question, and the rules involved in cleft sentences, like (6.2),
(6.2) Es war gestern, dass ich mit Orje {fiber Liebe sprach.
frY1..-.. V
W& all. 1 birvaN.= Wll.11 VLJG caVV46 ycQ,6ctuay INGQ,
the constraints on these rules was to assume that one rule was basic,
and was a component of the operations of the other three rules. But
shared by the four rules, rather than from some assumed common
there are a large number of transformations which obey the same con-
straints as the four rules that I had originally noticed, rules whose
the scope of the rule is unboundedly large, and then give examples
I know of (but cf. § 6.4) to the claim that only "reordering trans-
6.1.1,
protection!
I do not know how the rules that effect this conversion should be
...11".".Ff,r1R.Carmavy,
formulated.
are much more limited, for there are many question words that cannot
abstract noun like arrival, whose underlying lexical item does not
those in (6.4) is, it is clear that the rule which forms them must
to believe he is!
That this rule is subject to the CNPC, the CSC, and the
5
b. How brave it must be believed (?that) Tom is!
The reason that (6.11) is ungrammatical is the same as the one F'ven
until, and while. Michael L. Geis has proposed7 that all of these
387
time when, which may, by deletion of-ehe _NP at the time, result in
the constituent sentence for the phrase at that time, from which this
word derives, can be indefinitely far down ."the tree can be seen from
(6.12),
Sandra.
where the word when refers to the time of the shooting of Sandra. That
the CNPC, the CSC and the SSC can be seen from (6.13), (6.14), and
(6.15), respectively,
was awake.
388 01.
exemplified in (6.16):
For to phrases can modify noun phrases in the same way as relative
obligatorily just in case the embedded subject has not been deleted.
Thus (6.16) would be derived from the structure which underlies (6.18).
onions with.
Somehow the rule which forms these clauses must prevent a preposition
389
subject of the clause has been (or will be?) deleted -- nothing can
save a structure like (6.19), where the preposition with has pied
in any account.
the onions.
Constituents can be moved by this rule from indefinitely far down the
I am not sure whether this rule can relativize elements from within
VO ?tJF% .Ale,
.4D GI.
,ifrA.VVAL
eves 10. ". VW
YVUO +-
GOLOOVtAA.Al /4e4.4..^
N.VOLG
with to be announced.
7YL1,....
391
also do.
Sentence (6.26b) suggests that this rule must be able to prepose the
relative pronoun which, which stands for the sentence Fluffy is sick,
(6.23), and (6.29) show that it too is subject to the CNPC, the CSC,
wouldn't acknowledge.
.
realizes is certain.
The sentences in (6.30) show that the rule which forms as-clauses must
The sentences in (6.32) show them all to be subject to the CNPC, and
CSC, the SSC, and the LBC, respectively, while the sentences in
lortgograk01711TrivriTrivtmiwIlmsft "ftmeMPIIMITATtrir011
s n.)
474
(6.32) a. *It is this hat that I know the boy who is wearing.
was wearing.
the table.
b. *What the gloves and were on the table was this hat.
was wearing.
. ,
.43,114r14110"/PWRISIMWRIMIMMANNicV
S
394
convincing. But all that is at issue here is the fact that the set
father was.
The fact that the element half can precede the modified NP in
in (6.37),
for horoscopy.
but no analysis of these constructions has been deep enough for this
bounded in length:
CNPC, the CSC, and the SSC, as sentences (6.42), (6.34), and (6.44),
respectively, show-..
father was.
396
January 12th.
the fact that they both contain superlatives. What their deep
structures are in fact, and whether the same rules are used in
in (6.46).
drunk and.
been is believed.
6.1.2.
two rules to derive all of the above constructions. But in the case
(6.50)
VP
met in Vienna
a friend of mine
who was woslas in Europe, azi.r1
ins Europe.
home town.
(6.52)
NP
NP NP
was tragically evident
and
it
result.
400
would be produced.
However, since it is not known what the relative ordering of the rules
Formation or allstion.
to be subject to the CNPC or the SSC, because it, like the two
401
upward bounded, it can be shown to obey the CSC, for the a-sentences
Miami]NP kissed.
from Miami.
(6.58).
a. - [X -
.. 61. 1,....
1 2 3
[1 2 0]B#3
.....tomormomPrea 1 . _. - . ..-........2=...
.4,2
b. [and - - x1: IB
OPT
1 2 3
21/fl 0 31B
conjuncts which are also of the category B, and each of which either
definitely-is, -pregnant.
version of (6.60b) in which the claim is present and the one in which
seems clear that at least the CSC must constrain the operation of
rule (6.58), for I know of noone who finds the result of the conver-
was blonde.
in these hills.
reordering rule, and be subject to the CNPC and the CSC. That this
rule must also be subject to the LBC was pointed out in § 4.3,2.4
6.1.2.4. The next rule I will discuss in connection with the con-
concern us here.
405
(6.65) suggests.
(6.65) They said Tom would pay up, and pay up I'm
The rule is subject to the CNPC, the CSC, and the SSC, as can be seen
b.. *They said that Tom wouldn't pay up, but pay
(6.68) a. *They said that Tom would pay up, and pay up
(6.70) suggests.
marry Herman.
to marry Herman.
That this rule is subject to the CNPC, the CSC, and the SSC can be
must make
from some equally unknown deep structure, its statement
.'
407
(6.75) ,
?The more contented the nurses began to try
That this rule is subject to the CNPC, the CSC, and the
SSC can be seen from sentences (6.76), (6.77), and (6.78), respectively.
at -the--doctors.
at the doctors.
-""*Y._, ""'
408
I of it have a picture.
gauche de la maison.
'I see the end of 'the roof of the left wing of the
be subject to the CSC by the fact that (6.81a) cannot become (6.81b)
409
de la maison.
of the house.
17
b. *J'en vois-la porte du garage et le toit.
(cf. (6.83)),
got to grade.
(6.85b),
can be argued to be synonymous with any reading of (6.85a) and
respectively.
If their meaning is correct, they are the most obvious source for
(6.82) and (6.84). But if they cannot bethe source for these
(6.86)
I V ,N1
CT
can be inanimate.
the fact that the rule that produces them obeys the CSC and the LBC
and (6.89).
6.1.3.
6.1.3.0. In § 4.1.4 above, I argued from the fact that the rule
condition, (4.30), and to the CNPC (it is also subject to the CSC, .but
which will be made more precise in § 6.2 and §6.3 below). This is
only one of the possible conclusions: the other is that is not the
which exhibit the morphemes -er...than and as...as. Since these two
can be constructed.
(6.91). a. The sofa was longer than the room was wide.
This deletion operation is subject to the GINIPC, the CSC, and the SSC,
that Bill.is.
generally believed.
subject to the
There is another deletion rule which is
five cents.
by that much?
as in (6.97).
in (6.98).
and that it is subject to the CNPC, the CSC, and the SSC (cf. (6.100),
Cooz.
415
optionally,
the rule which converts (6.103a) into (6.103b), sometimes
sometimes obligatorily.
up.
(cf. (6.104)).
up.
be deleted: no grammatical
of clauses containing finite verbs will not
Go1/4 et:fie;-
416
a teaspoon.
into jacket.
pick it up.
pick up.
(6.110) a. The socks are ready for you to put them on.
may be the case that this deletion rule can operate over indefinitely
As was the case with the previous rule, this rule seems not to be
subject to the CSC and the LBC, as (6.113) and (6.114) show. Sentence
tial subject clauses, but I have not been able to 'find sentences like
(6.115b), where the deletion has become possible after the extra-
section.
garters on,
his bunk.
bunk.
ft p . Siaa4AMPIPPAPIPPlPP1P....-
418
on to be planned.
with ready hold true for a small class of similar adjectives, luch
Recently, however, several new facts have come to light which cast
me that bor.L :':,.117) and (6.118), which are not synonymous, would be
easy
(6.118) This violin is difficult, to play sonatas
hard
On.
the sentences of (6.119), which would have the came deep structure,
(6.120).
complement sentence.
conclusion that the deep subjects of'asy. in (6.117) and (6.118) are
420
(6.122):
(6.122)
NP
John is st
unless the above arguments can be gotten around.. This. rule appears
(cf. (6.123)),
than the SSC seems to be operative here, for neither (6.125a) nor
(6.125b) is grammatical.
6.2. Shapina21L11
6.2.0. In §§ 6.1.1 - 6.1.2, I gave a large list ofnreordering
are rules which perform such an operation, but yet are not subject
kind of place-marker.
.
422
(4.185) Topicalization
X NP Y
OPT
1 2 3
X NP Y
OPT
1 2
24 [1 [ 2 ] 3
+Pro
* on it J
424
ML r MS..w
1..G
^ r a.111.
IA 1114N ^v.^ nnA 1*1^f4
she's Greek.
(cf. (6.132)).
tight as a hoot-owl.
a hoot-awl.
425
back.
never use.
by the Revenooers.
suggests that the statement of the rule must make crucial use of
a variable.
each other,
he had no umbrella,
last night.
CSC, the SSC, or the LBC. But I showed in S 6.1.1.5 and in § 4.3.2.1
i 0 k.
copying transformations.
rule) if any of the lines in (6.140) were its structural change, but
(6.139)____ a - a - a - a4
1 2 3
1 2 3 4
(6.140) a. 1 3 2 4
b. 1 2130-4
c. 1 0 3 4 +2
d.441 0 312 0]
etc.
428
(6.141) a. 2+1 2 3 4
b. 1+2 2 3 4
c. 1 2 3 4+2
etc.
... no conjunct may be chopped ...", and similarly for the other
X -
[Pro] Y
1 2 3
El 2
[4.Po]
and (6.147):
Sentences like those in (6.146) show that this rule is unlike the
to main clauses.
430
b. I like beer, *I
?*me
we
c. * We'll go together,
us
they
d. * They can't stand each other,
them
have the feature [+ Pro] can still be argued to have the feature
(6.149) I
a. We'll do it together, you and
ne
he and she
b. They can't stand each other,
him and her
(6.150) ati
*He they let him go yesterday.
Him
b. *1 I like beer.
die
431
c. we'll go together.
Us
r
. J )
_ *They! ,
d. C } , they cant stand each other.
I Theml
l )
Once again, hawevei, I am not concerned with fine points
to show how the constraints'on this copying rule differ from those
. on the rule of N.? Shift, (5.57); for except for the various minor
course both be subject to the CNPC and the SSC, The sentences
but only on
as a constraint not on all reordering transformations;
minimal pair which shows the need for this distinction: that (6.153a)
is ungrammatical, but not (6.153b), shows that only NP Shift, and not
headlines.
;,'nor
c,
.4
433
c.
to register next term.
1
Didn't that guy who the Gam.; Warden and him
ormssmosIbe
appear to differ from (4.135), the more usual rule, only in that the
1119.01M,....1.44 Vr"
I
434
1.11 (6.154), which this rule leaves behind, are deleted, as would
is grammatical.
normally formed by a copying rule like the one responsible for the
gigigrojounk
/5
chopping rulelI know of whichillft not subject to
scrutiny.
from coordinate structures. The first is that there are cases where
.1
434
ic grnmplatic=11.
grammarians. But there are languages whose relative clauses are normally
formed by a copying rule like the one responsible for the sentences of
6.2.4.
S
implied in § 4.2.3. above, where I stated that the second conjoined
44 the NP
of (4.115) could be inserted into the first, in apposition
rule,
Pietro then the rule which forms these clauses is a chopping
and it violates the CSC. This rule would be one of the two chopping
are,
of
rules I know of which al= not subject to all the constraints
from coordinate structures. The first is that there are cases where
who.
"(6.155) Enrico, s the smartest of us all,
and h
. nn& f-to wnal,ca SeVen Qof'Anik,
are any, no, every, etc., appositive clauses cannot appear (cf. (6.156)),
A
Any }
who
(6.156) student, wears socks, is
and he
i°
Every 1
a swinger.
and that in these cases are the corresponding conjoined sentences also
impossible:
Any
(6.157) * No student is a swinger and he wears
Every "1.
socks.
These arguments are valid, and the facts they are based
(6.158) to be generated?
socks, a swinger?
(6.159)
and
for the arguments in § 4.2.4.3 showed ",hat such deep structures must
sentences like (6.158) from structures like (6.159) -- namely the fact
is not subject to the constraints, and the fact that such senten0,:is
must be wrong, and that another source must be found for appositive
clauses.
a very radical one. Since it appears that there must be rules of some
kind which convert one sentence into two (how else can the second
that there are also some rules which reverse the process. That is,
to account for the fact that the sentences of (4.156) are ungrammatical,
fAny
(6.161) *)No is a swinger. He wears
Istudent
very
socks.
However, the first argument that appositive clauses come from conjoined
and (6.165c)).
itself.
COW
439
23
c.* Jack will have a hole in my pocket.
And the structure underlying (6.167) can eventually become any one
output condition.
right-hand corner.
right-hand corner.
band corner.
CSC, and the LBC (I have as yet not been able to construct examples
440
CSC,
window.
window.
and it.
but the fact that (6.163a) can be converted into (6.164a) , and that
(6'.167) can be converted into (6.168c) and (6.168d) shows this rule
sister's nose.
sister's nose.
of her nose.
bought in Butte.
presented.
sitting in.
he
(6.172) a. ? Toby has a hole in the rug which
j
bought in Butte.
he
b. Prof. Hiatus had an error in the proof
*Sarah
presented.
jhe 1.
c. Fred had a snake behind the car was
Joe
sitting in.
which it injured.
(6.175c) shows.
TNT.
of no chopping rule that does not obey all the constraints of Chapter 4.
And I know of no copying rule which does obey them. Thus the distinction
1 2 3
1 . 0 31/2
producing (6.178b).
(6.177)
11-- VP
1
Bartlett Toli
6.179).
05
(6.179) a. * Bartlett and danced Toni.
/
exempt from the CSC, it must be some feature of the rule. The
of the rules; while the latter rule permutes to the end of the first
the former rule specifies that the second conjunct of the conjoined
to be the case that the constraints of Chapter 4 never affect any rule
unless that rule reorders one of its terms around a variable. This
of Chapter 4.
argued that if either the first and of (6.177) has been deleted, or
if the second has been converted into a preposition, the subject node
all these changes, and I do not know whether such an ordering can
be maintained.
for English, there are languages, like Japanese, where the conjunction
there are two additional cases, from English, which seem to require
below.
(6.182) shows.
%(1 .- :
Vy chopped
for
(6.184) X - [Al NP
oss VP 1S ]
NP
1 2 3 4 5
1 4 3 0 5
tarkiAg.
in (6.184), the chopped term merely moves over the constants in term 3.
(3A0b), (3.35b), and (3.36b) would not be generated. But the condition
him.
6.4. Islands
6.4.0. The fundaMental insight of this section is due to
Paul Kiparsky. In connection with some extremely important, but
still unpublished, research on complement constructions which he
is conducting, he pointed out that the that-clause in (6.190r1) has
a factive meaning, while this is not the case in (6.19010.
(6.190) a. Bill confirmed that Roger has eaten
[the cake I
b. f had eaten
Bill alleged that Roger ?has
;the cake)
One who utters (6.190a) is not only reporting an action of Bill's,
he is himself asserting that the content of the that-clause is true.
This is not the case with (6.190b) -- there the speaker merely
comments on Bill's action, without himself taking any stand on the
truth of the embedded sentence. One of the many ways that Kiparsky
has discovered this semantic difference to be paralleled by
syntactic differences is in the behavior of elements of the two
.kinds of that-clauses under chopping rules. Thus while the boxed
NP in (6.190b) can be questioned (cf. (6.191b)), the boxed NP
of (6.190a) can only be questioned with difficulty, if at all,
(cf. (6.19.1a)).
(6.191) a.?? What did Bill confirm that Roger had
eaten?
450
ontrIn?
anything.
anything.
hypothesis in (6.193).
6.4.1.
the CNPC, the CSC, and the SSC, respectively, and in the fourth,
The CNPC also correctly predicts that sentences like (5.731), where
rule (5.71) has gone down into a relative clause, are ungrammatical.
words like an, ever, and at all, which typically occur in environments
we -L in a delicatessen.
452
The only
e, travelers who anybody has
*Only the
whose determiner belongs to the set no, an v, a, sma, all, the first
(but not the second, third, etc.) the last, the Ad &. 4. est (cf. the
best steak I ever ate) (but not only the), etc., whether or
not the sentence containing the clause is negated. That this rule
But if the boxed [I- Affective] element of (6.196) has triggered the
change of the boxed some to any., then the environment for the rule
and this rule can go down into the relative clause, as has happened
in (6.197).
must follow (5.71), that the two rules cannot be collapsed into one.
453
mean.
(6.198), it will produce evert end . But now, the result of this
the rule to reapply in (recall that this rule could not have gone down
The rule must then be ablc to produce any2 on its second application,
and this any will provide yet a third environment for 'he rule to
reapply in, and so on down the tree. This is the only rule I know of
necessary.
(cf. the boxed ever). However, the fact that only the negative
clause to change to the circled ever shows once again that the rule
from (5.71).
rules are different, why are not both subject to the CNPC, since
that both are: the CNPC is stated in (4.20) in such a way that
dominated by a complex NP and from then being moved out of the NP.
455
since they are dominated by the NP, can cause the introduction
cannot.
above, I pointed out that the Case Markin; Rule must be restricted so
head NP, and I stated an ad hoc condition (lit which subscripts had
I hope that it will turn out to be the case that if there are
(6.193).
cake.
cake.
(6.204). .
cake.
for the fact that only or can appear in such sentences as (6.204) and
I
458
not only in that the feature [I- Indefinite] cannot go down into a
conjunct, but also in that the [I. Affective] element which broad-
Lakoff and Peters (op. cit.), (6.206a) and (6.206b) are derived
from the same underlying structure, the only difference being that
Maxine.
in Vienna.
Vienna.
459
than the above facts would indicate, however. So note that (6.207a)
Vienna.
Vienna.
and no
(6.209) a. No writer, playwright, speaks
nor any
clearly.
These sentences raise so many problems that I can only call attention
1,,
(K 414)111, Bill believes that Anna and he are
similar.
.re
A
1
believes
it
A /
VP
and NP NP be similar
I I
Anna Billi
other. That this does not happen (cf. the ungrammatical version
rules.
him to be
(6.213) Bill believes Anna and
* himself
similar.
rules are also subject to the SSC, but the pieces of evidence I
have been able to find to support this claim are based on very
and (6.214b), where the embedded subject clause has been extraposed,
is grammatical.
mat is certain.
acceptability of (6.214a).
outpu,t condition (3.27) will lower the
Does, therefore, the fact that rule (5.71) has applied to produce the
The
boxed mx in this sentence contribute to its unacceptability?
money is certain.
must be attributed.
student.
ten
s.aacz.by
414
"e"""".
C.4.44.7%11&11
Klima slipports his claim that (6.216b) and (6,217b) are instances
neither-tags, as in (6.218),
(particular) student.
student.
mo.4^1.
464
requires explanatinn,
28
certain.
The fact that the SSC can block (6.220b), if the rule of 1.1egatart
29
Incorporation is formulated as a feature-changing rule, thus
(5.98), could not go down into clauses headed by the word Xto 'that'.
V
sto on ijubil.
that he loved.
465a
it can be shown that the two Finnish rules which were discussed in
(6.225)),
a
(6.224) The man who I gave John ??this picture
*Ed's
of was bald.
1
a
(6.225) I gava Jack ?this picture of myself.
*Ed's
1
can be explainLtd, and the correct prediction can be made that other
a
(6.226) I didn't give Jack *this picture of
*Ed's
30
anybody.
toes.
466
and him
thimself 11.
in not known
is not certain
(6.230) That.anybody ever left at all
is impossible
'surprises me
is odd
467
.
In Japanese, it appears to be possible to violate
(6.231)
VP
NP
/\ S
VP sakana
tabeta
Biru. NP
0----1
sakana katta
(6.232) Biru
i
wa kare ga katta sakana o tabeta.
i
Bill he bought fish ate
the third person non-reflexive pronoun kare 'he, she, it' can
fkare4 1
(6.234) Biro_ wa ga kono sakana o
1
zibun
l i
he 11
6.4.3.
changing rules is the one which was stated in (5.77), and then
changed, then the triggering element must lie within the shaded
command A.
.
470
6)
s s
s
AA
LAA
A
A
There is an independently motivated principle of derived
(6.237).
471
example.
good tonight.
tastes good.
(6.23
fNNS
NP VP NP
r I
still tastes rood VAdverb
tonight
Bob
cooked
(6.240)
./4NP
//
/
/,
I
/
still tastes good
//
,141)
1 2
NP
what
473
e.g., the paradigm in (5.151), where the subject of will go can only
eaten up.
variables and which can move an element out of its strip; one
16.242) VP ]s - X - NP Y
1 2 3 4 5
4 4- 1 2 3 0 5
(6,243) a,
if.Y2P try
x_t
] EilLa.k.usc to
th..
King Ron
see
476
rigorous proof, along the lines sketched above, that the former
off its maximal strip, nor can any element of P which is not on
the main branch of the maximal strip of A (that is, the branch
statement of the CNPC, the CSC, the LBC or the SSC as not permitting
is cut into a smaller strip at that node. That is, if the main
subject position, the main branch (and the strip it is a part of)
6.5. Summary,
like those in (6.154), are the rules which can cross island
chopping
as pronominalizations, and would not obey the constraints on
is stated in (5.152).
rules of § 5.3 and the rules in § 6.1.3: while the former rules
clear, sense:
480
1
44., .4 4,,,r 4
, -, ,....
I:
.
481
Chapter 6
FOOTNOTES
grammar (cf., e.g., Harris (1957), section 11.2) that these two
The arguments that have been used are that the relative pronouns
and that both rules are subject to the same constraints. But
1
l
/
if the main argument of this chapter is correct, that all chopping
relate the fact that who replaces human nouns in questions, and
the fact that it also does so in rcomr-hrpq, the fact that whose
can be used for both human nouns (the boy whose body was lithe
snored on) and non-human nouns (trie car whose body was dented
(Whose body was lithe? ici,lhose body was dented?) causes problems
482
for those who assume that the two rules are the same. A more
men were there guarding the door?). To me, it seems most likely
such an identity.
e
483
(1964), fn. 2), indicates that these sentences are only gramma-
Compare, e.g., *How brave it is certain that Tom is! with Here is
6. This sentence is acceptable with the meaning "I don't see how
7. Personal communication.
still far better than (6.15a): Bill left when that noone else
Gilbert (1967).
485
II. A rough estimate of the perils that await the unwary grammarian
15. That is, the morpheme en'of it' must command the verb to which
some form such as celle -la that one there', nothing can save
result.
'I see the windows of the house and the door of the garage.'
as the house-gaIme. Notice that the reason that the CSC can
be "violated" here. is, in a strange new way, the same reason that
pronouns."
488
deep ways in which these two verbs behave the same under
23. That this sentence may be acceptable to some, with the meaning
concern us here.
construction.
Lakoff and Peters (op. cit.) argue, e.g., that the and in
daughter-adjoined to term 3.
a chopping rule which inserts the chopped nea into some other
of chopping rules.
31. In Ross (1967c), I show how this rule provides evidence that all
32. For a definition of the term 'proper analysis', cf. Chomsky (1955),
Fraser (1963).
491
Chapter 7
CONCLUSION
both too strong and too weak. A far more serious inadequacy in this
discussed, and it was shown that while these rules did not obey the
rules subject to the same constraints as the chopping rules for which
the constraints were first developed, but that it is only rules which
493
ridiculously small. This thesis has raised far more questions than
and not those which adjoin terms to the left of a variable? Why
oriented" that is, why should it be that there are phrase marker
and IIP's on the left branches of larger NP's all function the
i
psycholinguistic entities?
that they can now be asked is a major result of the thesis. For
as e.e. cummings has said, "always the more beautiful answer who
/
asks the more beautiful question."
i
if
495
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Chomsky, Noam (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton & Co.
The
Chomsky, Noam (1964b). Current Issues in Linguistic Theory.
Hague: Mouton & Co.
496
English and
Dean, Janet (1967). "Noun phrase complementation in
German." Unpublished paper, M.I.T.
in
Fillmore, Charles J. (1965b). Indirect Object Constructions
English and the Orderina of Transformations. The Hague:
Mouton & Co.
Fodor, Jerry A., and Jerrold J. Katz (1964). The Structure of Language:_
Readings in the Philosophy of Language. Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Halle, Morris, and Noam Chomsky (to appear). The Sound Pattern of
English. New York: Harper & Row.
Positions in
Keyser, S. Jay (1964). Review of Jacobson, Adverbial
kcal..Lat. To appear in Language.'
497
Lakoff, George, and John Robert Ross (1966). "A criterion for verb
phrase constituency." Mathematical Linguistics and Automatic
--Translation, Report No. NSF-17 to The National Science Founda-
tion, Harvard University, Computation Laboratory.
Lakoff, George, and John Robert Ross (in preparation a). The Abstract-
ness of Underlying Structures.
Lakoff, George and John Robert Ross (in preparation b). The Trans-
formational Component.
Lees, Robert B., and Edward S. Klima (1963). "Rules for English
pronominalization." Language, 39, pp. 17-28.
MEM.
...M1111
- --4,,t1.16111.000)Par
499
Zwicky, A.M., Jr., and S. Isard (1963). "Some aspects of tree theory."
Working Paper W-6674. Bedford; Mass.: Mitre Corporation.
500
BIOGRAPHY
son iof Dr. Douglas Allen Ross and Eleanor Campbell Mott Ross. I
go to the Poughkeepsie Day School from the third grade to the eighth
.1.1441,0(
eP111r 6-1k - 1 1:-/-:-.2 C/J4,2:). r
_I
, .
(7... a, '. Alt te / a )
a 4 . 3? a7P.PC
. .t-C
*.
j*2)
..s, .
I . o 1 21 7471 r`r is
k4 Io 4 4 111.
-V iT:-..e 1 I 1
.
4k I "C3 .t
(3.0-e) so Irc.(1.3.-/-.-1,)) etc
r /
Fe '311 3t: .3 31 re. C3 6)
(.)
a. )
.........
62 t:j /
34. !,,o
3 eigi:c (i C. i.
i
al./
krICA
ftit./Hg..
-
-..,
ia
.0.4,..c.s,,,
i/1 1."1',J.:^"k
I ..
6 ,, . / 6- 71.
.
tr.
f:t
v
ir'irs....'..-ATt'.'t:
I I'
...
,,i.,...,,..,;.......,,,,......,......,...
I ejt
?",:,..I. C : VC 1,..
'II'
1
It '
Ir 1)
.....
-.I
. .r.-.0. 4
/"-C. tel.
(5 1(6)
f Cu) ..1.'`j
V' 1-
D.14:1
C(
33:14 -c
i .. 1.. ( .4:,
( - P1 ,..",:i
a
f.) " ft
7 ='
5
1 i 17 C 1 / 2^
iv!
, ,i)
,
b. 1...),I. 4.
...,...,1
,
-.3.)0) L-#
4.)
q- C§ 1.1,a), '10
r
1... 1
4 AA14, j
t
. ;
"'''-e r
,tti.,(:).
11
,j
47 -12.e. (:-; 3 .
la ?, 130)
1,1)
13-) /4-2
3 -tr;..
/7:')
17T ar - aet)
zi-47cf.01.3,3)
)
.!
: (%1 . 3 -(1. .
/o 121 1 31 a Pi .:
Ism 4 j
.-=. 1.%
.;.
.4 .
I
::".......
A.
,
S.. 3)
)
h,-/ "
) ti?; i;z3
1.1
I 2. , 1,/
; .
1:".. ,,,,
/ 3p.),,
,A) _3%4
rn 447 14.50
)
,- ...),/f/AP-1,4?)1s.,A%;-
-.am* .i. i.; , id (i :./;:)r Ricp-,--.. a& ../ 6 ) 1
4.-53 3 -!0 ( 5.1?..Q . .
0 ) 469- 1)0
335- L3 » `-) ,34.1....) 341 JP-e-1 14
L,477
1%. 3 I Li 0- 92
.,..... "1.
,.
, -I .
,f
JJ p 1.
11.1 -
v.) e..1'1.1.)
1
,
LI ,. S4,i t'
v,,. tt .4s-7)/ )
, ,
44i)si......,.-,',0. ) ....,,,,
4 .3 i ...{..-- _., (4.1 i.
I....1; a cA4i 1f,A 71
. %
) }
)
ILO! 7? I LpC7-
) .. I :.fr..---
,) 1.41) r.e ( i t; .-1
t . 41 .
1 . ..1 ,,,.,) )i1' '1'.)/ ... ,','', t :it.)i
1 4t. 1
.4". 2.,2 t 1- 2- 3/
) ) ":2 )
-
CI
i.:"
Q Tit I 2
to
1 C.1t. 8e(1( be 4,
(t.iti3)
, .....amerta
" *0 : .
)k)
/,n
'1
61.3,a,Q) 3q0 117CA-
3 ele
ofts
1
; / ri 1 t ( sl.sa) C_._, .J .
)
» )1 33 6T3'tf-
G c
(2...
-
1 if `'. . 0 \ :7 2,2 C
1,L.a.4)) ye )44
" '''..."- ...1.
`a I .--, :.:...) !
a
, h,,17
6..3.3.3-- 6.3.3.0 )
-:". .y
ter t,
I \-1
s. -.
a
bil4,..../i
i
t f /4:1 ? °O)S g
ftrom. 6i e
.,. if ! , if lit13 c4). (f:c.).ci....-)..)
,1. 130.
dit /; ,
,qt.ft.,24.:e))gratif at-az s
(5f6; 13)